How are conference presentations professionally relevant?

Effective clinical innovations and the dissemination of research findings are key elements in the growth and development of the psychology profession. There are numerous avenues that enable authors to publish and present their work. Poster presentations at conferences are effective methods for communicating research findings and providing opportunities to meet with other researchers and clinicians to discuss the research being presented. Thus, these types of conference presentations play a key role in the proliferation of research.

In this week’s discussion, you will be submitting your proposal for the Week Five Virtual Conference. You may utilize relevant assignments from previous courses in this program or suitable projects from your professional life. See the PSY699 Call for Student Poster (Links to an external site.)Links to an external site. Presentations document for specific parameters and instructions on how to create your proposal. Following the guidelines presented in the document, create your proposal and attach it to your initial post in the discussion forum. Evaluate the impact participating in conference presentations may have on potential work settings and/or doctoral programs and comment on the following questions in your initial post.

  • How are conference presentations      professionally relevant?
  • What elements of the proposal process      were most difficult for you, and why?
  • What positive outcomes do you      anticipate will come from this process, which may be applied to potential      work settings and/or doctoral programs?Required Resources

    Articles

    Save your time - order a paper!

    Get your paper written from scratch within the tight deadline. Our service is a reliable solution to all your troubles. Place an order on any task and we will take care of it. You won’t have to worry about the quality and deadlines

    Order Paper Now

    1 .American Psychological Association. (2010).  Ethical principles of psychologists and code of conduct: Including 2010 amendments. (Links to an external site.)Links to an external site. Retrieved from http://www.apa.org/ethics/code/index.aspx

    · insertDescription

    2 .Caplan A. C.  (2008).  Denying autonomy in order to create it: The paradox of forcing treatment upon addicts . Addiction, 103(12), 1919–21. Retrieved from https://library.ashford.edu/ezproxy.aspx?url=http%3A//search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true%2526AuthType=ip,cpid%2526custid=s8856897%2526db=a9h%2526AN=35118770%2526site=ehost-live

    · The author of this article makes an argument that client autonomy can still be maintained when treatment is mandated.

    3. Manchak, S. M., Skeem, J. L., & Rook, K. S. (2014).  Care, control, or both? Characterizing major dimensions of the mandated treatment relationship . Law and Human Behavior, 38(1), 47–57. Retrieved from https://library.ashford.edu/ezproxy.aspx?url=http%3A//search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true%2526AuthType=ip,cpid%2526custid=s8856897%2526db=pdh%2526AN=2013-24290-001%2526site=ehost-live

    · The study described in this article examines whether mandated treatment relationships involve greater control than traditional treatment relationships. The principles of healthy adult attachment are also explored.

    4. Snyder, C. M. J., & Anderson, S. A. (2009).  An examination of mandated versus voluntary referral as a determinant of clinical outcome . Journal of Marital and Family Therapy, 35(3), 278–292. doi:10.1111/j.175-0606.2009.00118.x

    · The full-text version of this article can be accessed through the ProQuest database in the Ashford University Library. In this article, the authors examine the evidence related to the effectiveness of psychotherapy with mandated clients.

    5. Sullivan, M. A., Birkmayer, F., Boyarsky, B. K., Frances, R. J., Fromson, J. A., Galanter, M., . . . Westermeyer, J. (2008).  Uses of coercion in addiction treatment: Clinical aspects . American Journal on Addictions, 17(1), 36–47. doi:10.1080/10550490701756369

    · The full-text version of this article can be accessed through the EBSCOhost database in the Ashford University Library. While involuntary treatment in health care raises many clinical, cultural ethical, legal, philosophical, and political concerns, evidence exists that it can be an integral component of effective mental health treatment. Various dimensions of mandated treatment are explored in this article.

    6.Walker, R., Cole, J., & Logan, T. K. (2008).  Identifying client-level indicators of recovery among DUI, criminal justice, and non-criminal justice treatment referrals . Substance Use & Misuse, 43(12/13), 1785–1801. doi: 10.1080/10826080802297484

    · The full-text version of this article can be accessed through the EBSCOhost database in the Ashford University Library. This study examined differences in treatment outcomes between mandated and non-mandated clients referred for substance misuse with a focus on client-level factors.

    All of the requirement has been download except number 1. Number 1 you can go straight to the internet address.

    1.American Psychological Association. (2010).  Ethical principles of psychologists and code of conduct: Including 2010 amendments. (Links to an external site.)Links to an external site. Retrieved from http://www.apa.org/ethics/code/index.aspx

     

     

    2. Addicition

    Denying autonomy in order to create it: the paradox

    of forcing treatment upon addicts

    THE PRIMACY OF AUTONOMY IN

    PROVIDER–PATIENT RELATIONSHIPS

    American bioethics affords extraordinary respect to

    the values of personal autonomy and patient selfdetermination

    [1]. Many would argue that the most significant

    achievement deriving from bioethics in the past

    40 years has been to replace a paternalistic model of

    health provider–patient relationships with one that sees

    patient self-determination as the normative foundation

    for practice. This shift away from paternalism towards

    respect for self-determination has been ongoing in behavioral

    and mental health as well, especially as it is reflected

    in the ‘recovery movement’ [2–4].

    As a result of the emphasis placed on patient

    autonomy, arguments in favor of mandatory treatment

    are rare and often half-hearted. Restrictions on

    autonomy are usually grounded in the benefits that will

    accrue to others from reining in dangerous behavior [5].

    However, anyone who wishes to argue for forced or mandated

    treatment on the grounds that society will greatly

    benefit is working up a very steep ethical hill.

    A person has the fundamental right, well established

    in medical ethics and in Anglo-American law, to refuse

    care even if such a refusal shortens their own life or has

    detrimental consequences for others. Therefore,while the

    few proponents of mandatory treatment for those

    afflicted with mental disorders or addictions are inclined

    to point to the benefit such treatment could have for

    society, it is exceedingly unlikely that any form of treatment

    that is forced or mandated is going to find any

    traction in American public policy on the basis of a consequentialist

    argument, great as those benefits might be.

    However, is benefit for the greater good the only basis

    for arguing for mandatory treatment? Can a case be made

    which acknowledges the centrality and importance of

    autonomy but which would still deem ethical mandatory

    treatment for addicts? I think it can.

    INFRINGING AUTONOMY TO

    CREATE AUTONOMY

    People who are truly addicted to alcohol or drugs really

    do not have the full capacity to be self-determining or

    autonomous. Standard definitions of addiction cite loss

    of control, powerlessness and unmanageability [6]. An

    addiction literally coerces behavior.An addict cannot be a

    fully free, autonomous agent precisely because they are

    caught up in the behavioral compulsion that is addiction.

    If this is so, at least for some addicts, then it may be

    possible to justify compulsory treatment involving medication

    or other forms of therapy, if only for finite periods

    of time, on the grounds that treatment may remove the

    coercion causing the powerlessness and loss of control.

    Addicts, just as many others with mental illnesses and

    disabilities, are not incompetent. Indeed, to function as

    an alcoholic or cocaine addict onemust be able to reason,

    remember complex information, set goals and be orientated

    to time, place and personal identity; but competency

    by itself is not sufficient for autonomy. Being

    competent is a part of autonomy, but autonomy also

    requires freedom from coercion [7]. Those who criticize

    mandatory treatment on the grounds that an addict is

    not incompetent and thus ought not be forced to endure

    treatment are ignoring this crucial fact. Addiction, bringing

    in its wake as it does loss of will and control, does not

    permit the freedom requisite for autonomy or selfdetermination.

    If a drug can break the power of addiction sufficiently

    to restore or re-establish personal autonomy then mandating

    its use might be ethically justifiable. Government,

    families or health providers might force treatment in the

    name of autonomy. If a drug such as naltrexone is

    capable of blocking the ability to become high from

    alcohol, heroin or cocaine [8,9], then it may release the

    addict from the compulsive and coercive dimensions of

    addiction, thereby enhancing the individual’s ability to be

    autonomous. If a drug or therapy can remove powerlessness

    and loss of control from the addict’s life, then that

    fact can serve as an ethical argument allowing the mandating

    of treatment. If naltrexone or any other drug can

    permit people to make choices freed from the compulsions

    or cravings that would otherwise control their behavior

    completely, then it would seem morally sound to permit

    someone who is in the throes of addiction to regain the

    ability to choose, to be self-governing, even if the only

    way to accomplish this restoration is through a course of

    mandated treatment.

    Of course, it would not be ethical to force treatment

    upon anyone if there were significant risks involved with

    the treatment but new drugs, such as naltrexone, appear

    safe and effective for those addicted to heroin and perhaps

    cocaine, and should also prove so for alcoholics. The

    mechanisms behind the drug are well understood [8,9],

    and in some populations this drug has been used for a

    long time to reduce the cravings of addiction safely and

    EDITORIAL doi:10.1111/j.1360-0443.2008.02369.x

    © 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 Society for the Study of Addiction Addiction103, 1919–1921

    effectively. Mandating treatment requires that the intervention

    carry minimal risk as the patient cannot consent,

    but some interventions may be able to meet this admittedly

    difficult standard.

    Nor would it make moral sense to force treatment

    upon someone, restore their autonomy successfully and

    then continue to force treatment upon them in their fully

    autonomous state. The restoration of autonomy is the

    end of any moral argument for mandatory treatment.

    Similarly, efforts to restore autonomywould not justify

    continuous, open-ended use of drugs or therapy in

    addicts. There must be some agreed-upon interval, after

    which treatment must be acknowledged to have failed

    and other avenues of coping with addiction to alcohol or

    drugs pursued.

    PRECEDENTS FOR MANDATING

    TREATMENT IN THE NAME

    OF AUTONOMY

    Interestingly enough, despite the emphasis on autonomy

    in law and ethics in American health care there are situations

    where the ethical acceptability of the rationale of

    autonomy restoration in permitting mandatory treatment

    is already accepted. Consider what occurs in rehabilitation

    medicine. The short-term infringement of

    autonomy is tolerated in the name of long-term creation

    or restoration of autonomy.

    Patients, after devastating injuries or severely disfiguring

    burns, often demand that they be allowed to die. They

    say: ‘Don’t treat me’, or they may insist that: ‘I can’t live

    like this’. In evaluating their requests, no one would be

    able to question seriously their competency. They know

    where they are. They know what is going on. However,

    staff in rehabilitation and burn units almost always

    ignore these initial demands. Patient autonomy is not

    respected. Why?

    What rehabilitation experts say is that they want to

    allow an adaptation to the new state of affairs: to the loss

    of speech, amputation, facial disfigurement or paralysis.

    They know from experience that if they do certain things

    with people—train them, counsel them, teach them

    adaptive skills—they can encourage them to start to

    ‘adjust’ [10].

    There are, admittedly, still peoplewho say at the end of

    a run of rehabilitation: ‘I don’t want to live like this’. The

    suicide rate is higher in these populations. Nevertheless,

    at least initially, rehabilitation specialists will say that

    they have to force treatment on patients because they

    know from experience that they can often encourage

    them to accept their new state of affairs. The normal

    practice of rehabilitation immediately after a severe

    injury is to mandate treatment, ignore what patients

    have to say, and then seewhat happens. If they still do not

    want treatment after a course of rehabilitation then their

    wishes will be respected [10].

    The rehabilitation model is precisely the model to

    follow in thinking about the mandatory use of a drug

    such as naltrexone for the treatment of addiction. The

    moral basis for mandating treatment is for the good of the

    patient by rebirthing their autonomy. How long and

    whether someone ought to be able at some point say: ‘I’ve

    done this for 6 months, I’m finished, I want to get high

    again’ is a challenging problem, but it is not the key one.

    The keymoral challenge is to open the door to temporary

    mandatory treatment. That can be achieved, ironically,

    on the grounds of autonomy. It may press current ethical

    thinking to the limit, but mandating treatment in the

    name of autonomy is not as immoral as many might

    otherwise deem forced treatment to be [7]. Once competency

    and coercion are distinguished, it is clear that both

    are requisite for autonomy. Mandatory treatment which

    relieves the coercive effects of addiction and permits the

    recreation or re-emergence of true autonomy in the

    patient can be the right thing to do.

    Acknowledgement

    The author is grateful for the support of the Scattergood

    Foundation in writing this essay.

    Declaration of interest

    None.

    Keywords Addiction, autonomy, mandatory treatment,

    naltrexone, paternalism, right-to-refuse treatment.

    ARTHUR CAPLAN