Ethics in the Community
Ethics in the Community
Post on at least three separate days. There is only one discussion this week. The prompt is below the list of requirements. The requirements for the discussion this week include the following:
Save your time - order a paper!
Get your paper written from scratch within the tight deadline. Our service is a reliable solution to all your troubles. Place an order on any task and we will take care of it. You won’t have to worry about the quality and deadlines
Order Paper Now- You must begin posting by Day 3 (Thursday).
- You must post a minimum of four separate posts on at least three separate days (e.g., Wednesday, Friday, and Saturday, or Thursday, Friday, and Sunday, or Thursday, Saturday, and Monday, etc.).
- The total combined word count for all of your posts, counted together, should be at least 600 words, not including references.
- You must answer all the questions in the prompt and show evidence of having read the resources that are required to complete the discussion properly (such as by using quotes, referring to specific points made in the text, etc.).
- In order to satisfy the posting requirements for the week, posts must be made by Day 7 (Monday); posts made after Day 7 are welcome but will not count toward the requirements.
- Be sure to reply to your classmates and instructor. You are encouraged to read posts your instructor makes (even if they are not in response to your own post), and reply to those as a way of examining the ideas in greater depth.
- All postings (including replies to peers) are expected to be thought out, proofread for mechanical, grammatical, and spelling accuracy, and to advance the discussion in an intelligent and meaningful way (i.e., saying something like “I really enjoyed what you had to say” will not count). You are also encouraged to do outside research and quote from that as well.
- For more information, please read the Frequently Asked Questions
.
Discussion: Ethics in the Community
In Chapter 1 of your text, you saw how moral reasoning involves moving back and forth between general, abstract ideas like principles and values and particular concrete judgments about what is good or right, and seeking to find a kind of agreement or equilibrium between those.
In Chapters 3, 4, and 5, you were introduced to utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics. Each of these ethical theories represents different ways of reasoning about ethical questions, based in different account of the principles, values, and other conceptions that inform the “abstract” side of the dialectic.
In this course, and in much of life, the “concrete” ethical issues that receive the most attention are frequently those that elicit passionate responses and widespread debate, affect large numbers of people, involve matters of deep significance like life and death or fundamental rights, and so on. However, as important as these issues are, there is often a limit to how much impact most individuals can have on such matters; instead, the place where ethics and moral reasoning have their greatest impact is in one’s local community. Thus, in this final discussion board, you will demonstrate your grasp of the relation between the abstract ideas in one of these theories and a concrete ethical issue or social problem in your local community.
- Engage the community:
- Begin by finding an ethical issue or social problem that currently impacts or has recently impacted your local or regional community (such as your neighborhood, town or city, county, school district, religious community, or something of similar scope to any of these).
- Briefly summarize the issue or problem, and provide a link to a news article, video, or some other resource that documents the issue or problem so that your fellow students can learn more about it when formulating their responses to you.
- Apply the theory:
- Next, choose one of the ethical theories and discuss how the moral reasoning of the theory might be used to address or resolve the issue or problem.
- Evaluate the reasoning:
- In evaluating the application of the moral theory you may, for example, consider one or more questions like:
- Does this differ from the way this issue is currently being addressed?
- Does it present a better response than another ethical approach would?
- Does the theory present an adequate response to the issue, or does it leave significant aspects of the issue unresolved?
- Does applying the theory to this issue raise other problems or concerns?
- In light of this issue, are there ways the principles or values of the theory might need to be modified from the form that we studied in class?
2 Skepticism About Ethics
Bet_Noire/iStock/Thinkstock
Learning Objectives
After reading this chapter, you should be able to:
• Explain what it means to be a moral skeptic.
• Explain the notion of moral relativism and how it differs from moral objectivity.
• Discuss challenges to relativism.
• Explain the notion of egoism and how it differs from the notion that moral standards are unconditional.
• Discuss Glaukon’s challenge from Plato’s Republic and identify the main claims made in the story.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
38
Section 2.1 Introduction to Skepticism
2.1 Introduction to Skepticism In contemporary usage, skepticism means a doubt that a belief or claim is true. We often use this word to refer to general doubts about all claims of a particular sort. For example, a reli- gious skeptic might have doubts about claims pertaining to the existence of God, the possibil- ity of knowing anything about God, and so on. A global warming skeptic might doubt claims that human activity is the main cause of average global temperature rise, or a 9/11 “truther” might be skeptical about claims that the terrorist attacks in New York City and Washington, D.C., were exclusively the doings of al-Qaida (as opposed to being supported by the U.S. gov- ernment). Likewise, many people regard the claims of politicians, salespersons, and media personalities with doubt and suspicion.
Similarly, a moral skeptic—in the way we will be using this term here—will doubt common beliefs about morality itself. It is important to note that we are not referring to people who doubt specific moral claims, such as the claim that eating animals is wrong or that abortion is morally justified. Nor are we referring to those who doubt the truth of certain general moral theories or principles, such as utilitarianism or deontology. If we recall the discussion of the landscape of moral philosophy from Chapter 1, claims about concrete moral problems like eating animals or abortion fall under applied ethics, while claims about the general rules, principles, and values that should inform our judgments and choices fall under normative ethics. The kind of skepticism we are discussing in this chapter involves the more basic kinds of claims that fall under the scope of metaethics.
Specifically, we will consider the reasons one might hold doubts about two commonly assumed features of morality itself:
1. Moral standards are objective. 2. Moral standards are unconditional.
The forms of moral skepticism we will consider in this chapter raise doubts about those two features.
1. Relativism doubts whether moral standards are objective, instead maintaining that they are only true or false relative to a culture or individual.
2. Egoism doubts whether moral standards are unconditional, instead maintaining that they are only good if they serve an individual’s self-interest, which in turn implies that it may be better for individuals to act contrary to moral standards if they can.
We will focus a section of this chapter on each of these. First, however, it is important to note three features common to each form of skepticism.
First, skepticism is not mere doubting or contradicting. One can doubt a claim without hav- ing any basis for doing so, and one can contradict any claim by merely saying the opposite of what another person says. Neither of these are worth taking seriously by themselves, because there is no good reason for those doubts or contradictions.
The kinds of moral skepticism we will examine aim to provide such reasons. Indeed, the word skepticism itself comes from the Greek word skeptesthai, meaning “to examine” or “to consider.” Since the skeptic uses reason to undermine certain assumptions about morality,
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
39
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
we have every right to test the strength of his or her reasons. Perhaps doing so will lead us to question whether the reasons to doubt morality are good reasons (we might even become skeptical of the skeptics, so to speak). In other words, being skeptical about morality does not mean that one has abandoned the use of reason in thinking about what morality is, why it matters, and related issues. We should therefore approach skeptical views with as much criti- cal thought as a skeptic approaches the views he or she calls into question.
Second, the general features of morality that skeptics question—such as its objectivity and unconditionality—are ones that most moral systems take for granted. Accordingly, skeptics of morality generally provide an alternative explanation for why most people take these fea- tures for granted. A skeptic will have to explain why certain assumptions about morality have such a grip on us, despite the fact that we are deeply misguided (as they would claim). In addition, just as we can test the strength of the skeptic’s reasons for doubt, we can test the strength of his or her alternative explanation.
Third, we mentioned previously that the kind of skepticism we consider in this chapter is not primarily concerned with applied ethical issues like abortion or eating animals; nor does it focus on the general principles, rules, and values with which normative ethics is primarily concerned. Rather, it questions metaethical ideas like moral objectivity or unconditionality. However, questioning these ideas can have significant implications with respect to norma- tive and applied ethics.
The relation between metaethics, normative ethics, and applied ethics is comparable to the way we might think of a house. The strength of the roof depends on the strength of the house’s framework—the walls, support beams, and so on. But the framework needs a strong founda- tion if it is to support the roof. If the foundation has serious problems (e.g., the concrete has major cracks, the ground is giving way), then the support system will be unstable. If the sup- port system is unstable, then the roof is weak and liable to give way. We can think of concrete moral judgments as the “roof,” normative theories as the “framework,” and metaethics as the “foundation.” Moral skepticism questions the strength of the foundation, and, by implication, the strength of the framework and roof.
As we examine the different forms of skepticism, we should ask ourselves if the skeptic has provided good reasons to be skeptical of our common beliefs and assumptions about ethics. Has he or she provided a satisfactory alternative explanation for why we have these common beliefs and assumptions that adequately accounts for the role that ethics plays in our indi- vidual lives? And what would be the broader implications of accepting his or her skeptical claims about ethics?
With these thoughts in mind, we will examine skepticism about moral objectivity.
2.2 The Relativist Challenge American restaurant goers know that when a waiter or waitress provides good service, he or she deserves a decent tip; withholding a tip when good service has been provided is usually regarded as disrespectful. In Japan, however, the opposite is the case: Providing a tip is often a sign of disrespect. Similarly, consider that most Westerners believe that the way to show
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
40
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
respect to the deceased is to cremate or bury their bodies, while leaving a body out in the open is the epitome of disrespect. However, in Himalayan cultures—partly because there is not much wood for burning and the hard ground makes it difficult to dig graves—it is custom- ary to leave the bodies of the dead out in the open to be consumed by animals and the ele- ments, which is regarded as dignifying.
Countless other examples can be raised about behaviors that one culture regards as ethical but another regards as unethical, and vice versa. Over the past century or two, as contact with other cultures has become increasingly common, many people have come to doubt whether their way of behav- ing and judging is the only “right” way.
Even within contemporary Western culture, there has been increased emphasis placed on individual self-determination of the values and principles that guide one’s life, which leads to doubts about whether any single set of values and principles should be authoritative for all. Indeed, bitter and sometimes violent conflicts often arise when one per- son or group is perceived as imposing its moral views on others. Instead, people commonly preface their expressions of moral commitment with phrases like “in my opinion” or “in my personal view”—the implication being that they have no right to suppose that others should agree.
These factors have contributed to a sense that moral judgments are not true or false in any objective sense but are instead relative to a culture or individual. Moral objectivity is the view that at least some moral truths are independent of the beliefs and values of any particu- lar culture or individual. By contrast, relativism rejects moral objectivity. Instead, relativism holds that the truth of moral standards depends entirely on the beliefs and values that a cul- ture or individual subject happens to hold. This means that if a culture or individual believes or values certain ideas, the associated moral judgments are relatively true (i.e., true for them); if they lack those beliefs and values, any conflicting moral judgments are relatively false (i.e., false for them).
Before examining this more closely, it is important to note that most people who think care- fully about what relativism means ultimately conclude that it has limits and cannot be entirely correct. Most people hold many deep beliefs that conflict with the relativist position, and there are significant ways in which the position itself may be incoherent. Moreover, relativism is not a normative ethical theory like utilitarianism or deontology; that is, one cannot invoke relativism as a reason to affirm or deny a particular moral judgment, as if it were an alterna- tive to, say, the principle of utility or the Categorical Imperative. For instance, one cannot say something like “According to utilitarianism, stealing this item would be wrong, but according to relativism it would not be wrong.” Before going into detail, we will look more closely at the general claims of relativism itself.
Jupiterimages/Stockbyte/Thinkstock Different attitudes toward giving and receiving gifts represent one example of how cultures can have different ethical standards.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
41
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
Two Types of Relativism Thinking back to the examples above, when an American claims that not tipping a waitress, leaving a dead body to rot in the open, or stoning a woman to death are wrong, one might suppose it is only wrong according to modern American culture; according to another culture, these behaviors may in fact be right. Such a view would be considered cultural relativism, since it acknowledges that within a particular culture, given a set of characteristic beliefs, val- ues, and customs, certain behaviors might be right or wrong; it denies, however, that the same judgment can be applied to similar behaviors in another culture with a different set of charac- teristic beliefs, values, and customs. In other words, it denies that there are any judgments of right and wrong that extend across all cultures regardless of whether their beliefs, values, and customs support those judgments. One might also subscribe to subjectivism, which is the view that matters of right and wrong are ultimately relative to the values that each individual subject recognizes and affirms.
In either form, relativism can have great appeal. It can be taken as a sign of respect for other cultures or individuals by refusing to deny or denounce what they find important and mean- ingful or by refraining from imposing oneself on others. It can help us avoid the conflicts that can result from disagreeing over ethical matters. It can be an expression of honesty and humility, in that it helps us presume to know more than we really do about ethical questions. Finally, it can be a way to acknowledge that much of what we believe and how we think people should act has been shaped by our own culture and upbringing.
Challenges to Relativism One can appreciate the appeal of relativism without being a relativist about everything of ethical significance; as we mentioned above, most people are relativists about some ethical matters but not all of them. The limits of both cultural relativism and subjectivism become clear when one considers personal experiences, the implications that relativism has, the con- sistency and coherence of the relativist position, and the interconnectedness of cultures and personal lives.
Personal Experience To understand the problems with the relativist position, think about your own experiences for a moment. Each one of us has a story to tell about how we came to be where we are, which includes elements such as community, society, religion, family, friends, and many other factors that influenced and shaped who we are and what we believe. Each of these elements is quite diverse in and of itself, incorporating many different beliefs and forms of life (think of the diversity within American society, for instance). To come out of a culture is thus to have been exposed to a range of different and often conflicting perspectives out of which we have to form our own identity, values, and moral beliefs. Moreover, none of us has all of the same beliefs and values that our parents did or that we ourselves had when we were younger, and these beliefs and values continue to change throughout our lives in profound or subtle ways.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
42
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
At least some of the ways we arrived at the beliefs and values we have is the result of reflec- tion and experiences that lead us to affirm, reject, or modify aspects of our own prior per- spectives, the perspectives with which we were raised, and those of our surrounding culture. That is, our own development was not wholly determined for us by some outside factor like family or culture, nor was it arbitrary or accidental. Rather, we had some reason indepen- dent of our culture to accept or reject certain elements of it. Likewise, we had some reason independent of how we were raised to accept or reject certain elements of our upbringing, and some reason independent of our subjective perspective would have led us to change that perspective. In short, our own experiences point to reasons for or against moral convictions that are independent of culture, upbringing, and personal values and thus not merely relative to those factors.
We can strengthen this observation, though, by looking more closely at what holding a relativ- ist position would involve and whether it would have implications that conflict with much of what we otherwise believe about morality.
Implications of Relativism First, what are the implications of relativism? When we become aware that different cultures have different views on whether it is respectful to tip a restaurant server, we may come to think that there is no objective truth about tipping that applies to all cultures. Let’s assume this is correct. We might then be tempted to think that all matters of respect or disrespect—or any other matter of ethical importance—are relative to one’s culture. But do we really think this? What would such a view imply about other matters of moral significance?
For example, consider an issue such as whether certain kinds of people should be enslaved or exterminated. During the 1930s and 1940s, German Nazis engaged in the mass extermination of those they regarded as unworthy and unfit, such as Jews, Gypsies, homosexuals, and peo- ple with certain disabilities—we call this event the Holocaust. Relative to the beliefs, values, and customs characteristic of German Nazis, Jews and others deserve no respect, and thus it may have been true (for that culture) that the atrocities of the Holocaust were not wrong but necessary, even noble. Similarly, relative to the beliefs, values, and customs characteristic of southern White culture in America prior to the freeing of the slaves in the 19th century, it was true (for that culture) that people with dark skin did not deserve the basic freedoms owed to Whites and thus that slavery was not wrong; in fact, many in that culture regarded slavery as good and right.
If we accept the cultural relativist position, two important implications follow. First, cultural relativism implies that we would have to abandon the judgments most of us make about the absolute rightness or wrongness of certain kinds of actions. For example, since exter- minating Jewish people, enslaving Blacks, or persecuting and killing those of different faiths are morally justified relative to the beliefs, values, and customs of cultures that engage in those actions, we cannot legitimately say that they are wrong, even if our culture disapproves of them. Likewise, our own rejection of such things cannot legitimately be called right, since this judgment is merely relative to our culture. However, hardly anyone accepts this: Most people maintain that regardless of the beliefs, values, and customs of the cultures that engage or engaged in such actions, their behavior is or was despicable and wrong, period. In that case one is not a relativist about such matters.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
43
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
The second implication of cultural relativism is that we must reject any notions of cultural progress and decline. In addition to no longer permitting slavery, American society no longer allows the segregation of Blacks and Whites in schools, restaurants, buses, and many other contexts, as it did long after the end of slavery. American society also once refused women the right to vote and allowed children to work long hours in mines and factories, but none of these practices are legal or generally accepted nowadays. Recently, homosexuals have been given the right to marry and serve openly in the military, more women are being given equal pay for equal work, and increased efforts are being made to ensure that children and those with disabilities are protected. There may be controversy regarding whether certain specific cultural changes represent progress or decline, but in either case, in the words of the philoso- pher James Rachels (2003), “that is just the sort of transcultural judgment that, according to cultural relativism, is impossible” (p. 22). In other words, if one were to judge that American
The Bacha Bāzī
Recent military activity by American and other Western forces in Iraq and Afghanistan has embroiled them in some challenging cultural conflicts. One of the most challenging and contentious conflicts concerns the practice in Afghanistan of bacha bāzī, which those in the West would call pederasty or pedophilia. In short, bacha bāzī involves powerful warlords and other prominent men taking prepubescent and adolescent boys as their sexual slaves. This practice seems to have been present in some Asian cultures for centuries, and though it was officially outlawed by the Taliban, the ouster of that regime by Western forces in 2002 removed the penalties for participating in this practice. Thus, it became more commonplace among the Afghan warlords and police commanders that the U.S. and allied forces depended on to secure the nation (Londoño, 2012).
Is the practice of using vulnerable boys as sexual slaves merely wrong relative to our own culture, or is it wrong no matter the cultural traditions, beliefs, or practices?
One way to frame this question is to ask whether a child has a set of basic human rights that would be violated by this practice. This is certainly the view taken by the United Nations and the 196 countries that have signed its Convention on the Rights of the Child, among which is a provision that protects children from sexual abuse (UN News Center, 2015; United Nations, 1989). These provisions are based on the “recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family” (United Nations, 1989, para. 1), which is to say that it recognizes that all people have certain rights above and beyond particular cultural beliefs and practices, among which is the right of a child not to be sexually abused.
Now, denying the relativist position and acknowledging such rights does not settle all of the ethical issues, for there is still the question of how one should respond when confronted with practices like bacha bāzī. The U.S. military’s policy has been to look the other way so as to maintain good relationships with the Afghan leaders who perpetrate this abuse (Goldstein, 2015). However, there have been several cases of soldiers disobeying such orders and attempting to prevent the abuse (Goldstein, 2015). Whether they were right to do so is a question we cannot address here, but surely we can presume that they would not have done so unless they regarded the actions of the abusers as a violation of objective standards—that no one should abuse children regardless of whether such abuse is accepted by a culture.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
44
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
culture has progressed by outlawing slavery and segregation and by granting women the right to vote, one must deny cultural relativism. Likewise, if one were to judge that American cul- ture has declined in certain ways, one must deny cultural relativism. Why?
The reason is that any notion of a culture’s progress or decline must refer to standards that are independent of the culture as it happens to be. If increased racial or gender equality is to count as progress, it is because we think that racial or gender equality is good, and so a cul- ture that has more equality is better than one that has less. Or if we think that a culture has declined in certain ways, it would be because we regard certain norms as good and judge that the culture has veered from those norms. Either way, we are judging a culture by standards that are independent of the beliefs, values, and customs they happen to have. This is contrary to the relativistic view that there are no such independent standards. If we accept relativism, then we have no basis on which to hold that cultural changes like the elimination of slavery or granting women the right to vote is progress or that any changes could represent decline.
Similar problems arise for subjectivism. While we can appreciate that individuals within a culture have a wide variety of lifestyles and conceptions of what is good and worthwhile and that a “one-size-fits-all” perspective is often unjustified, most people recognize limits to this relativistic attitude. For instance, Omar Mateen, who killed 49 people at a gay nightclub in Orlando, Florida, in 2016, may have acted consistently with his beliefs, as do others who per- petrate terrible atrocities. But few of us would be content to suppose that the wrongness of such actions is merely relative to our own personal values. Moreover, as we previously dis- cussed, many of us have changed our moral views and behavior as we have matured, and we experience this change as one of personal growth or progress. Just as the notion of cultural progress is difficult to square with a belief in cultural relativism, the experience of personal growth in one’s moral convictions and choices is inconsistent with the view that moral truth is only relative to the beliefs and values that an individual happens to have. The best we can say is that we had certain beliefs and made certain choices at one point in our lives and sim- ply changed at a later point. Again, however, most of us experience that kind of change not as arbitrary, but as one of genuine development. All of this implies that one is not a relativist about moral matters.
In short, the implications of relativism are that we can no longer sustain judgments that things such as slavery, genocide, terrorist attacks, rape, child molestation, and others are truly wrong; nor can we do adequate justice to the notion of cultural progress and the experience of personal moral development. Thus, we find that while most people are relativists about some matters of cultural or personal difference, very few people are relativists about all such matters.
Consistency and Coherence of Relativism The second set of challenges to relativism has to do with the consistency and coherence of the relativist position. Think back to the appealing aspects of relativism: It may seem to show respect for other persons or cultures, can help us avoid conflicts, and can be an expression of honesty and humility. Notice that each appealing aspect refers to some value that the rela- tivist position seems to affirm or embody: respect, peace, honesty, humility, and so on. All of these are adduced as good reasons to adopt a relativist position.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
45
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
However, respect for other cultures or for individual choices has a particular value that many of us affirm but some others may not. Peace is also something that many, but not all, value. Honesty and humility are generally regarded as virtues, but not everyone agrees. If the value of respect, peace, honesty, and humility are to count as reasons in favor of relativism, this value must be independent of whether others recognize it; in other words, they must have objective value. But if this is the case, then relativism must be false. Thus, what we thought were reasons in favor of relativism turn out, upon examination, to be reasons to reject it.
To see how defenses of relativism undermine relativism by appealing to nonrelative values and principles, think about the consistency and coherence of a few common expressions one might hear in support of relativism:
• “We should not pass judgment on other cultures.” In other words, passing judgment on other cultures is wrong. What should we say about a culture that passes judgments on other cultures? Are we not saying that what they do is wrong? By saying that what they do is wrong, are we not still passing judgment?
• “Who am I to say that what someone else does is wrong?” This saying means that no one has a right to say that what someone else does is wrong. But what if someone does say that what someone else does is wrong? Doesn’t that mean that they have done something wrong?
• The Bible says, “Judge not, lest ye be judged” (Matthew 7:1). The Bible seems to indicate that we should not pass judgment on another. But the Bible also contains a great many ethical teachings that seem to be presented as objec- tively true. Many of those teachings challenged the prevailing culture and its leaders to whom Jesus was speaking in this verse. Does this suggest that this verse should be understood as a warning against the objective wrong of hypocrisy rather than as a support of relativism?
One can see the inconsistency that arises when phrases like these are used to express or sup- port a relativist view. There may be contexts in which the sentiment they express is appro- priate, but the bottom line is that these expressions endorse values or principles that other cultures or persons may not share or ones that apply in some contexts but not all. In doing so, they do not support a position of moral relativism but rather one of nonrelativism.
Respect for Others Not only does the relativist’s endorsement of respect, honesty, and humility imply these ideas’ objective value, but their value may even be undermined if we were to adopt a consistently relativist position. Take respect, for example. As we noted before, a relativist position is often taken to express respect for other persons or cultures by refusing to pass negative judgment on their beliefs and practices. However, what does respect really mean? Generally, it means that we recognize some kind of value or merit in whatever we respect. We are making a judg- ment that a person or culture is worthy of respect.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
46
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
Moreover, as the philosopher Mary Midgley (1981) notes, “To respect someone [or some cul- ture], we have to know enough about [the person or culture] to make a favourable judgment” (p. 69). In other words, to show respect requires a certain level of understanding of a person’s or a culture’s beliefs and practices that allows us to recognize their potential value and merit. However, the level of understanding that would justify respect and praise has to allow for the possibility of negative judgments as well. “It is hardly possible that we could praise them effectively,” Midgley observes, “if we could not, in principle, criticize them” (p. 71). What does she mean by this?
The popular radio show A Prairie Home Companion includes a regular segment about the fic- tional town of Lake Wobegon, Minnesota, where “all the children are above average.” The joke behind this description of the community is that it is impossible: No child can be above aver- age except in comparison to other children who are average and still others who are below average. In other words, describing a child as above average requires us to have a standard for “average” according to which a child can be judged to be at, above, or below. By declaring that all children are above average, one is essentially saying that no child is above average, since all are at the same level. Thus, the praise and esteem implied by the term above average is meaningless.
Just as being above average constitutes a positive judgment about a child, being worthy of respect is a positive judgment about a person’s or culture’s beliefs and practices. But for the positive judgment to be meaningful, there has to be the possibility of a negative judgment as well. Just like the positive judgment that a child is above average must entail that some chil- dren are average or below average, the positive judgment that cultural beliefs and practices are worthy of respect must entail that some cultural beliefs and practices are not worthy of respect. If we declare that all cultural beliefs and practices are worthy of respect, that is just as vacuous as declaring that all children in a community are above average.
To put it another way, if we refuse to judge other cultures at all, we “are not taking the other culture seriously” (Midgley, 1981, p. 73), a point that can be applied to judging other persons as well. It is a powerful idea: Would a positive judgment like “worthy of respect” be meaning- ful or significant if there wasn’t the possibility of negative judgments, that some things are not worthy of respect?
Consider this same idea as it pertains to a value like honesty. Imagine you were seeking a friend’s honest opinion on your new outfit. Would you trust her thoughts if you knew that she would never say anything negative? If you suspected that she would say you look good no matter what, would you turn to her if you really wanted to know if the outfit looked good? Probably not. Genuine honesty, like genuine respect, depends on the possibility of a negative judgment; otherwise, any positive remark would be empty and meaningless.
In short, by insisting that all value judgments are merely relative, a stance of relativism entails that we cannot make positive judgments about another culture or individual, including the judgment that they are worthy of respect. Thus, relativism does not, in fact, show respect for others, as some defenders maintain.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
47
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
Intellectual Humility Perhaps the most common and familiar way to defend relativist attitudes is by using phrases like “Who am I to say what’s right or wrong for someone else?” Such phrases seem to call us to intellectual humility: How can we pass judgment on others when we know so little of their circumstances or when we cannot be sure our judgments are well grounded? This is important, but we can only account for its importance if we reject relativism and accept there are certain standards by which we can, at least in principle, judge others and ourselves. Why is this?
As we saw in Chapter 1, acting on the basis of reasons—which is fundamental to human life— depends on the capacity to judge that certain choices are better than others. It is easy to see that in many everyday situations, such as deciding on the best car to buy or how to treat an illness, our own knowledge is limited; we may not have better judgment than someone else, and we can probably learn a lot from others if we open ourselves up to their judgment and perspective. Because of these limitations, humility and a willingness to learn from others seems to be in order.
But this only makes sense if there are, in fact, better or worse judgments on such matters. Why suppose that we may be limited in our knowledge of how to treat an illness or buy a car if there were no such thing as better and worse judgments about them? If humility and being open to learning from others is important, we must suppose that there are some judgments that are good and others that are not.
In most everyday situations, this is not hard to see: If a doctor recommends a certain treat- ment for an illness, it would be absurd to suppose that the effectiveness of this treatment is relative to one’s beliefs and values. Likewise, if humility and an openness to learning from others are important regarding ethical matters, then we would have to presuppose that there are some ethical judgments that are good and others that are not. To put it another way, if we think we might have something to learn from another people or cultures, we have to suppose that their ethical judgment might be better than ours, but this logically entails that their ethi- cal judgment might also be worse than ours in certain respects. Both of these possibilities, however, imply that relativism is false, and phrases like “Who am I to judge?” actually deny relativism rather than support it.
At this point you might be thinking, “Relativ- ists don’t have to suppose that there aren’t better and worse ethical judgments at all. They simply maintain that what’s ‘ethically better or worse’ for one person, culture, or society might not be the same for another.” As a factual matter, this is true—individu- als and cultures have many different ethi- cal beliefs. But remember that relativists do not simply point out that different people or
Thinking About Relativism
Relativism is more than the acknowledg- ment of differences in beliefs; it is the claim that we have no way of comparing the merits of different ethical beliefs and values.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
48
Section 2.2 The Relativist Challenge
cultures happen to have different ethical beliefs and values; they maintain that we have no way of comparing the merits of these different beliefs and values. What critics of relativism argue, however, is that the sense many people have—that we should not be quick to judge and that we should exercise humility in the face of such differences—is based on the assumption that there are nonrelative truths on ethical matters about which we may have only limited understanding. But this seems to call for an honest and open consideration of the different beliefs and values rather than simply refusing to pass any form of judgment whatsoever.
Cultural and Interpersonal Differences There is one final challenge to relativism, which is perhaps the most powerful of all. Cultural relativism seems to rest on the idea that cultures are completely isolated from each other, such that one culture would be so disconnected from another that they could not understand each other enough to judge each other’s beliefs or practices. Subjectivism would seem to pre- suppose something similar about our inability to understand, and thus judge, the values and beliefs of another person. But is it plausible to suppose that we are disconnected from each other to such a radical degree?
To suppose so would be to suppose that the beliefs and values of different cultures or indi- viduals developed and were shaped in isolation, but this is clearly not the case. With very few exceptions (such as isolated tribes in the Amazon rain forest), all cultures, along with their beliefs and values, have been shaped and formed by their encounters with others; as Midgley (1981) puts it, “all cultures are formed out of many streams” (p. 74).
Early human societies had to overcome similar obstacles and challenges in the face of a hos- tile natural world, despite differences in conditions such as climate and resources. Migra- tions, wars, and trade brought different cultures into contact, and they had to find ways to relate to each other. Modern societies are even more interconnected than previous societies due to technological advances. The notion of a culture that is radically disconnected from oth- ers is difficult to imagine, and the idea that an individual can be so disconnected as to rule out judgment on others’ values and beliefs is even more implausible. Thus, there is good reason to suppose that we may find common, rationally justified grounds for many moral values and principles, and that a relativist stance is not justified on the grounds of cultural or interper- sonal differences.
Limited Relativism We have presented relativism as a form of skepticism about whether values, principles, and norms are objectively true—that is, true for all cultures and individuals. Relativism maintains instead that their truth is only in relation to a particular culture or individual, such that what- ever is true for one culture or individual is not necessarily true for another. It is important to note that we have been considering a somewhat extreme form of relativism that maintains that one culture or individual cannot pass judgment on the moral standards of another. Reject- ing this form of relativism does not necessarily mean that all moral standards are objectively true; there may be good reasons to suppose that at least some moral standards are relative. Distinguishing between those that are merely relative, objective, or somewhere in between
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
49
Section 2.3 The Egoist Challenge
requires critical thought, open-mindedness, and a willingness to engage in dialogue with the other. By the same token, immediately declaring a different moral view as simply wrong on the one hand, or merely different (i.e., neither right nor wrong) on the other would be too hasty in most cases and would fail to demonstrate respect and intellectual humility or acknowledge the interrelated- ness of cultures and individuals.
Moreover, rejecting relativism and accept- ing that there may be objective moral truths does not mean we would necessarily expect all people to accept or acknowledge those truths. Similarly, we may have good reason to pass judgment on other cultures’ or indi- viduals’ beliefs and practices, but that should be distinguished from a judgment about the specific culture or individual. That is, I may believe that a certain cultural practice is wrong (perhaps because it demeans women, for example), but that does not necessarily entitle me to declare that members of that culture or the culture as a whole are bad.
Having concluded this discussion of the relativist’s challenge to morality, we now turn to skepticism about the other assumption we identified—skepticism about the unconditionality of moral standards.
2.3 The Egoist Challenge We all know the feeling: you really want to do something, but you know that it goes against the moral rules. Sometimes, though, you’re pretty sure you could do it and not get caught. What holds you back?
We have been taught to regard certain kinds of behavior as good and other kinds as bad, and often these rules stand in contrast to what we feel inclined to do. These claims about good and bad might come from our parents or teachers, religious authorities, media personalities, and many others trying to tell us how we ought to live. Are these claims unconditional in the sense of describing standards for how one ought to live regardless of whether they directly benefit us as individuals? Or are their rationality and force conditional on this benefit?
One reason for supposing that such behaviors are merely conditional is to regard them as nothing more than social conventions or sets of rules that society imposes on its members whose primary purpose is to constrain them from doing what they would otherwise want to do. Why might we have such conventions? Lots of possibilities spring to mind. Such conven- tions help maintain social order, for instance. If there was no prohibition on stealing, we could not be secure in holding on to the things we need to live our lives. Prohibitions on murder
Going Deeper: Are Ethical Standards Merely Expressions of Attitude?
In addition to relativism and egoism, some philosophers have questioned the assumption that there are such things as moral properties or moral facts at all. Instead, they maintain that moral statements are expressions of feeling or attitude that are neither true nor false. One such theory is called “emotivism,” which you can read more about in Are Ethical Standards Merely Expressions of Attitude? in the Going Deeper section at the end of the chapter.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
50
Section 2.3 The Egoist Challenge
ensure that our lives are relatively safe, while prohibitions on lying ensure that we can trust other people, which is vital to most social interactions. These conventions also protect weaker members from being taken advantage of by stronger ones, and moral values such as generos- ity and beneficence compel those who have more to share with those who have less. We can also imagine how certain groups of people might use such conventions to exercise power over others, in terms of keeping them in line and making them easier to control.
Whatever explanation we might have for why we have these conventions, one thing to notice is that they are all consistent with the assumption that each individual is and/or ought to be primarily concerned with his or her own interests and benefit. We call this kind of view egoism. If egoism were true, we could understand moral standards as social conventions designed to ensure a certain level of cooperation and to keep us from seeking our own advan- tage at the expense of others. However, if morality is nothing more, and each of us is com- pletely self-interested, why should we respect those conventions?
Most social conventions—especially those codified as formal rules or laws—come with sanc- tions or punishments for breaking them. Therefore, one obvious reason to respect them is that we do not want to be punished. But what if you could avoid punishment? What if you had the ability to transgress these moral conventions and not get caught? Would there be any rea- son to be moral? Therefore, the questions at the heart of the egoist challenge are, do we only have reason to be moral if doing so benefits us, and would we be better off acting immorally if doing so had greater self-benefit?
Glaukon’s Challenge This is not a new question; in fact, humans have been wrestling with the question of “Why be moral?” for ages. Twenty-five hundred years ago, the great philosopher Plato raised this issue in his most famous text, the Republic. Plato explored philosophical ideas mostly through fictional dialogues, many of which featured Plato’s real-life teacher Socrates as a main char- acter. Prior to the passage we will examine, Socrates had proposed that the person who lives a just life (similar to what we would call a moral life) is better off than the person who lives unjustly (or, roughly, immorally). Acting justly isn’t good simply because it happens to fulfill one’s interests or because it helps maintain social order, Socrates claimed. Rather, he main- tained that the life of justice is good in itself. In other words, those who act justly live the truly best kind of life, and so justice is worth choosing even when it might seem that acting unjustly would be advantageous. This is a familiar idea to us: We often hear about the value of integ- rity, or doing the right thing even when no one is looking. However, it is this very idea that is called into question in Glaukon’s challenge.
In the passage, Socrates’s friend (and Plato’s own real-life brother) Glaukon is challenging him on the concept of integrity. He does so by offering a story designed to question Socrates’s claim that justice is truly best. It is important to note that Glaukon is most likely playing dev- il’s advocate; there is no reason to suppose that Glaukon actually disagreed with Socrates. In offering his story, Glaukon can be considered part of a dialectical movement. He is suggesting a concrete case (though fictional and far-fetched) that forces Socrates to clarify his account
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
51
Section 2.3 The Egoist Challenge
of why justice is truly good and injustice is truly bad, despite the fact that we are often inclined toward injustice.
As you read the text, try to identify Glau- kon’s primary claims and how the story he tells helps him argue for those claims. Read “The Ring of Gyges” in the Primary Source section of the chapter, then return to this point in the book.
In Glaukon’s speech, he puts forth three pri- mary claims:
1. No one is willingly just. 2. Justice is a social convention that benefits the weak. 3. The best sort of life is that of the unjust person who seems just.
How does Glaukon argue for these claims?
Claim 1: No One Is Willingly Just Imagine a situation in which you can do anything you choose and not incur punishment or social condemnation. This is the scenario Glaukon invokes when he tells the story of the Ring of Gyges. In this story, a poor shepherd finds a ring that can make him invisible by turning it a certain direction. With this newfound tool, the shepherd realizes that he can get away with many things that would be considered unjust, now that he no longer risks being caught and punished. If Socrates is right, finding the ring should make no difference as to whether the shepherd respects principles of justice. Since justice is good in itself, Socrates claims, the possibility that one can get away with injustice is irrelevant. In Glaukon’s story, of course, the shepherd decidedly does not see things the same way and instead engages in murder, seduc- tion, and other illicit activities.
Dialectical Reasoning
Recall that dialectical reasoning involves moving back and forth between abstract principles and concrete cases in such a way that the concrete cases challenge us to revise and refine the abstract principles, leading us to form more refined judgments about the concrete cases.
Ethics FYI
Symbolism in the Ring Notice that when the ring is facing outward toward others, the wearer is visible to others and thus must be concerned with how society views him. By turning the ring inward toward himself, he becomes invisible to society, and thus his true inner condition becomes manifest. It is this inner condition with which both Socrates and Glaukon are ultimately concerned. (Author’s note: This interpretation is indebted to one of my students, David Plunkett.)
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
52
Section 2.3 The Egoist Challenge
Glaukon suggests that when the shepherd respected and abided by principles of justice before he found the ring, he never did so willingly. He knew that if he engaged in murder, seduction, and the like, he would likely be caught and punished and would lose his reputation. The risks outweighed any benefits of unjust behavior, and so the shepherd acquiesced to the system of justice in place. We know that he did so unwillingly by the simple fact that once he acquired the means to avoid such negative repercussions, the standards of justice went out the window.
Glaukon thinks that if we are honest, we will agree that even if a person we would normally regard as just or moral were to acquire the means to act unjustly without consequence, his
Ancient and Modern Fantasy Stories
The Ring of Gyges story contains themes that may be familiar to some readers from literature and film.
Those who are familiar with The Lord of the Rings by J. R. R. Tolkien will no doubt recognize the similarity of that story and Plato’s (indeed, the idea of a magic ring of invisibility is present in the myths of many cultures). In each myth, there is a ring that grants its wearer the power of invisibility, but it also corrupts its wearer in some sense. Glaukon would say that the only corruption is in terms of the standards of society, but that in reality the person who uses the ring to his advantage is living better than before. Tolkien’s account presents a different picture, one of not just external but internal corruption.
A similar scenario is presented in the 1993 film Groundhog Day. In the movie, Phil Connors (played by Bill Murray) wakes up to the same day over and over. No matter what he does, the day is reset and there are no negative consequences—to himself or anyone else—from his actions.
When Phil realizes this, he is elated. “It’s the same thing your whole life,” he says. “Clean up your room. Stand up straight. Pick up your feet. Take it like a man. Be nice to your sister. Don’t mix beer and wine, ever. And, oh yeah, don’t drive on the railroad tracks” (Albert, Erikson, White, & Ramis, 1993), after which he proceeds straight onto a railroad track. He spends the next part of the movie doing things that he would never be able to do because of society’s rules. Here is a man who, like Glaukon’s shepherd, felt like he had to obey those rules to remain respectable and avoid condemnation, while deep down he wished that he could blow them off and have fun. Once the negative consequences are no longer a factor, he sees no point to the rules anymore, and he can just let loose: “I’m not gonna play by their rules anymore!” (Albert et al., 1993). As one of Phil’s drunk companions put it when asked what he would do in such a situation, “I’d just spend all my time drivin’ fast, gettin’ loaded and gettin’ laid” (Rubin & Ramis, 1992, p. 45).
However, Groundhog Day takes a significantly different turn than Glaukon’s story. After indulging himself for a while, Phil finds himself in a state of such depression and misery that he attempts to kill himself over and over, only emerging from that state once he no longer concerns himself merely with satisfying his own interests and desires. Instead, he pursues artistic excellence, helps others in need, and finds himself caring for others for their own sake, not simply for what he can get out of it.
Can The Lord of the Rings and Groundhog Day provide a clue as to how one might respond to Glaukon’s challenge?
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
53
Section 2.3 The Egoist Challenge
or her actions would be no different from those of an unjust person; both the just and the unjust would follow the same path. If this is true, it shows that no one is just willingly, but only because they are compelled to be. Glaukon seems to be saying that we are interested only in ourselves—satisfying our own wants and desires and securing our own advantages—which brings us back to egoism. According to the egoist view, everyone is ultimately self-centered, which implies that no one is truly just, there are no truly selfless actions, and we only have reason to respect justice and morality or care about the needs of others when doing so ben- efits us.
Is Glaukon right? Are even the most ethical of people only acting that way to build a good reputation, avoid condemnation and punishment, and so forth? Naturally, there are people (perhaps you are one of them) who would insist that they would continue acting ethically even if they could act otherwise and get away with it. What would someone defending Glau- kon’s claim say about such persons? Perhaps they are deluding themselves because they are so used to the idea that acting unethically would be too risky. Perhaps they would feel a strong sense of internal guilt at pursuing their own advantages at the expense of others.
Notice, however, that the feeling of guilt is itself a form of punishment, albeit one that is imposed on ourselves rather than by an outside force. If ethical standards are simply con- straints on what we really want to do, as Glaukon’s account maintains, then a powerful way to ensure that people abide by them would be to condition them in such a way that they would punish themselves for breaking those standards. Feelings of guilt would be one such form of punishment. However, the presence of these feelings does not necessarily mean that the behaviors one would feel guilty about are wrong. It may only mean that one has been condi- tioned by society to feel bad about certain behaviors.
Huck Finn and the Guilty Conscience
In Mark Twain’s classic novel Huckleberry Finn, set in the days of slavery, the title character befriends a runaway slave named Jim. Even though Huck recognizes Jim’s humanity and regards him as a friend, he is plagued by feelings of guilt over the fact that he isn’t fulfilling his supposed duty to turn in a runaway slave. At one point, he contemplates turning in his friend but ultimately decides against it.
Thinking that the decision to not turn in Jim was wrong, morally speaking, Huck says:
I got aboard the raft, feeling bad and low, because I knowed very well I had done wrong, and I see it warn’t no use for me to try to learn to do right; a body that don’t get STARTED right when he’s little ain’t got no show—when the pinch comes there ain’t nothing to back him up and keep him to his work, and so he gets beat. Then I thought a minute, and says to myself, hold on; s’pose you’d a done right and give Jim up, would you felt better than what you do now? No, says I, I’d feel bad—I’d feel just the same way I do now. Well, then, says I, what’s the use you learning to do right, when it’s troublesome to do right and ain’t no trouble to do wrong, and the wages is just the same? (Twain, 1885/2001, pp. 87–88)
(continued on next page)
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
54
Section 2.3 The Egoist Challenge
Huck Finn and the Guilty Conscience (continued)
Huck feels a sense of guilt at not turning in a runaway slave. Yet he recognizes that he would have felt guilty if he had turned Jim in as well, since Jim is his friend. Thus torn, he decides that if he’s going to feel guilty either way, he might as well do what he wants to do, rather than what he’s “supposed” to do, given the standards of his society. After all, he figures, he’s a bad kid anyway, so there’s no point to trying to do what’s “right.”
Later, still wrestling with this decision, Huck composes a letter to Jim’s owner telling her where her runaway slave is. Just before sending it, he reflects:
I took it up, and held it [the letter betraying Jim] in my hand. I was a trembling, because I’d got to decide, forever, betwixt two things, and I knowed it. I studied a minute, sort of holding my breath, and then says to myself: “All right, then, I’ll go to hell”—and tore it up. It was awful thoughts and awful words, but they was said. And I let them stay said; and never thought no more about reforming. (Twain, 1885/2001, p. 192)
Huck was brought up in a society that held to the view that Black people could be the property of Whites, and if a White person’s property escaped, it was the moral responsibility of other Whites to return that property to its rightful owner. He regarded his reluctance to do so as a sign of moral depravity and experienced feelings of guilt at that failure. These days, we would not consider Huck’s reluctance to betray Jim to be a failure at all. However, it goes to show that feelings of guilt do not, by themselves, indicate that one’s actions are truly wrong.
In similar fashion, someone defending Glaukon’s claims might acknowledge that people may feel guilt at the thought of acting immorally even when they would not be punished or condemned. However, these feelings would be considered a sign that someone has been conditioned to regard such actions as wrong. In reality, says someone defending Glaukon’s claims, the person would be better off overcoming such feelings and pursuing the personal advantages that come with possessing the ring.
If egoism is right, moral standards constrain the basic motivation we all have to pursue our individual interests above all else. This implies that we would rather avoid such constraints if we could, and thus we are not willingly just; rather, we are just only because we fear punish- ment, whether internal or external. If this is the case, why are moral standards such a power- ful force in society?
We considered a few possibilities earlier: These constraints help maintain social order, ensure safety and security, and protect weaker members of society. Notice, however, that these are good reasons for us to want others to respect these constraints; they aren’t necessarily rea- sons why we as individuals should respect them. What if we could get away with injustice while everyone else respected the constraints that maintained social order? If we would ulti- mately prefer that situation, that indicates that we don’t willingly do what is just, but rather we do it because we cannot get away with acting otherwise.
In the real world, of course, rings of invisibility do not exist; but we can think of it as repre- senting the real power some people may have to act unjustly without the risk of punishment.
© 2018 Bridgepoint Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Not for resale or redistribution.
55
Section 2.3 The Egoist Challenge
All real societies have stronger and weaker members. The stronger members have the means to obtain more of what they want; they can find ways to secure what they desire through force, persuasion, or money. They also have the means to prevent others from trying to take advantage of them, and they have less need for the generosity of others. Weaker members of society, on the other hand, are those who lack such means. They are thus the ones who would benefit most when the rest of society complies with standards of ethics and justice. Hence, we arrive at Glaukon’s second claim.
Claim 2: Justice Is a Social Convention That Benefits the Weak If Glaukon’s egoistic view is correct, no one really wants to act morally. However, we recognize these standards because they seem to be good for soci- ety—it is good for us if people are not murdering others and stealing things. But who most benefits from this?
To see Glaukon’s answer, imagine two people: Big Jim and Tiny Tim. Big Jim is strong, well connected, wealthy, and charismatic. Tiny Tim is weak, a bit of a loner, poor, and socially awkward. Both Big Jim and Tiny Tim are self-centered and want as many per- sonal advantages as possible, regardless of how that might harm others. For obvious reasons, Big Jim is much better at getting what he wants than Tiny Tim. In fact, when Big Jim goes after something, it often ends up harming Tiny Tim in some way.
Is there anything people like Tiny Tim can do to prevent people like Big Jim from doing what- ever they feel like, gaining all the advantages for themselves, and stepping all over the Tiny Tims?
What if we established a system of rules that constrained people’s capacity to pursue what- ever they want for themselves?
People like Tiny Tim are already constrained by their own weakness, especially when com- peting against people like Big Jim. Such a system of rules would level the playing field a bit more, which benefits the Tiny Tims when it comes to their capacity to pursue what they want and avoid harm from the Big Jims. But it hinders the Big Jims, since they wouldn’t be able to use their superior means as freely as before.
- In evaluating the application of the moral theory you may, for example, consider one or more questions like: