Becoming a Good Thinker

Becoming a Good Thinker

The goal of this assignment is to progress as a questioner and, therefore, as a thinker. For this assignment, select an important problem faced by society today (e.g., income inequality, gun violence, online privacy), and construct three questions that will result in critical thinking using the assignment template.

  • In the template, under the first column, provide your own original questions related to your chosen important problem.
  • In the second column, identify domain of thinking.
    • Examples of these can be found on pages 139–140 of your textbook.
    • In the third column, list the intellectual standards and element of thought that relates to your question. Briefly explain why the question is important in this context (i.e., the elements of thought or reasoning that led you to this thinking).
    • The eight elements of thought can be found beginning on page 62 of your textbook.
    • The intellectual standards are on page 58 of your textbook and are defined on page 103.
  • In the fourth column, label your question as fact, preference, or judgment.
    • This information can be located on pages 126–127 of your textbook.

Tomas, Kindergarten

Part of a special educator’s responsibilities include understanding the characteristics of the major disability categories and how the characteristics affect typical development. When conducting observations and consulting with staff who work with students with disabilities, teachers must be able to articulate the differences in development and prescribe appropriate interventions. Understanding the effect of culture and language development must also be considered in meeting student needs.

Tomas, Kindergarten

Tomas entered Mrs. Richards’ kindergarten classroom at the beginning of the school year with great excitement! He showed great interest in learning and being in the classroom with other students. As the school year progressed, however, Tomas’ excitement quickly turned into frustration. He struggled with recognizing the letters in his name, identifying different shapes, and consistently could not follow two-part instructions. He also was dramatically less able than his peers to focus on a task. His frustrations have led to impulsive actions. Mrs. Richards has called a meeting with his parents to address her concerns.

Harper, 3rd Grade

Harper attends Sunset Elementary School and is in a class with 25 other third graders. Harper loves her teacher Mrs. Hernandez and struggles when a substitute takes her place. She excels in math and tends to get bored when the other kids in her class struggle. Harper also loves reading about the weather, somewhat obsessively, and can share weather facts and details for hours. She enjoys going to school, but does struggle with the loud noises a school brings. In school assemblies, for instance, she becomes overly upset about the noise level and tends to rock back and forth to calm herself. She also does not like fire drills and has refused to leave the classroom because of the sound of the fire alarm. Instead, she will flop to the ground, kick, and cover her ears.

Austin, 5th Grade

Austin was 9 years old when he was hit by a car while riding his bike on the sidewalk. He broke his arm and leg and hit his head very hard. When he came home from the hospital he looked just fine, but he needed help. Now back at school, there are changes in Austin that are hard to understand. It takes Austin longer to do things, and he has trouble remembering. He cannot always find the words he wants to use. Math is hard for him now, but it was his strongest academic area before the accident.

Mary, 9th Grade

Mary and her mother recently moved to the school district from Mexico after divorcing her father, who still lives in Mexico. Mary and her mother now live with Mary’s uncle, his wife, and five kids. Mom is working two part-time jobs to make ends meet so they can eventually afford to move to an apartment nearby. Mom can speak and read English, but is often working during times when Mary is home from school. Mary speaks some English, but only reads and writes in Spanish. She is reading at the third grade level in Spanish and has difficulty writing paragraphs. Writing is limited to simple sentences. Mary likes mathematics and can complete simple algebraic expressions, and is close to grade level in geometry. She does struggle with word problems.

Essay

Selecting one of the student scenarios above address the following prompts in a 750-1,000 word essay:

  1. Explain how language, culture, and family background influence your student of choice.
  2. Summarize the cognitive, linguistic, social, and emotional development of the student described within the scenario.
  3. Identify three instructional approaches that respond to the needs of the student described within the scenario.
  4. Explain why teachers need to be committed to respecting students’ individual strengths, interests, and needs to promote each student’s growth and potential.

Support your response with at least three scholarly resources.

Prepare this assignment according to the guidelines found in the APA Style Guide, located in the Student Success Center. An abstract is not required.

Social Constructivism

reading

  • Phillips & Soltis: Chapter 6
  • Wenger: A Social Theory of Learning Preview the document
  • McLeod: Vygotsky (Links to an external site.)  https://www.simplypsychology.org/vygotsky.html
  • Schunk: Chapter 6 (Read Only the Following Pages/Sections)Preview the document
    • 240 (Vygotsky S.C. Theory) – 248
    • 250 (Socially Mediated Learning) – 233
    • 269 (Peer Assisted) – 271
    • 274 (Summary) – 277

Commentonat least 3 Classmates’Posts (approximately  150 -300 words each)§

– comment must address the R2R prompt and your classmate’s response substantively; if you agree or disagree, provide reasoning and rational evidence from the readings to support your position

– build on the ideas of what your classmate has written and dig deeper into the ideas

– support your views through research you have read or through your personal and/or professional experiences§demonstrate a logical progression of ideas

– comments need to be thoughtful and substantive; not gratuitous comments like “this was a good post” or simply that “you agree”. Simply congratulating the writer on their astute insights is insufficient.

– cite the readings in your response by using proper APA Style format and conventions.

classmate 1

 

Hello everyone!

Social learning theory is described as being a “theory of learning process and social behavior which proposes that new behaviors can be acquired by observing and imitating others.” Learning is a social experience in a lot of different ways. Social interactions are critical in learning. We learn so much from interacting with others and our environment. The fundamental principles of social learning states that “learning occurs when observing other’s behaviors and the resulting outcomes of those behaviors.” Observation and mimicking are the first forms of learning as a child. Peer collaboration, reciprocal teaching, apprenticeships, and scaffolding are all examples of learning using the social model. In other words, we learn from everything around us. We learn from our interactions as it stimulates developmental processes and fosters cognitive growth, the information that is “learned” is transformed into knowledge.

Lev Vygotsky is a constructivist theorist; he placed more emphasis on the social environment being a factor in learning. Vygotsky’s theory stresses that “the interaction of interpersonal (social), cultural-historical, and individual factors as the key to human development. Vygotsky considered the social environment critical for learning and thought that social interactions form learning experiences” (Schunk, page 242). One of the fundamental concepts presented by Lev Vygotsky is that a person’s interactions with the environment aid in their learning. Social interactions are necessary for learning to take place, and that knowledge is gained when two or more people interact with one another. Another concept would be self-regulation, which involves “the coordination of mental processes such as planning, synthesizing, and forming concepts” (Schunk, page 252). Additionally, human development happens through cultural practices and the use of the cultures tools such as language and symbols; language is “the most critical tool, and develops from social speech, to private speech, to inner speech.” Lastly, the zone of proximal development (ZPD) is the “difference between what children can do on their own and what they can do with assistance from others” (Schunk, page 243).

Jean Piaget and Lev Vygotsky were both believers that children are actively involved in their own learning and in the development of new schemas or understandings. However, Vygotsky’s theory was different from Piaget’s theory in a number of ways. First, Vygotsky assumes that cognitive development varied across cultures whereas Piaget stated that it was universal across all cultures. Second, Vygotsky believed cognitive developed occurs from social interactions from guided learning within the ZPD and when the children and their partner co-construct knowledge together; whereas Piaget believed cognitive development happened when children constructed knowledge on their own and independently. Third, Vygotsky places more emphasis on the role of language in cognitive development; and cognitive development results from the internalization of language. Whereas Piaget thought that language depended on thought for its development (thought comes before language). Last, Vygotsky stresses that adults are important because they transmit their culture’s tools of intellectual adaptation that the children internalize, whereas Piaget emphasized the importance of peers and the interactions promoting social perspective taking.

A community of practice is a group of people who share an interest/profession/or a craft. Communities of practice are everywhere; they are in schools, work places, homes, and within our hobbies or interests. We all belong to communities of practice, which change over the course of our lives. Learning is a part of our everyday lives, and is part of our participation in our community. Communities of practice impact learning by providing a way for people to exchange information, ask questions, express ideas and opinions, share best practices, and support one another. It is through the process of sharing information and experiences with the group that members learn from each other, and have an opportunity to develop personally and professionally.

Social Constructivist approaches have impacted teaching and learning in so many ways. This week’s reading has been a much needed reminder of how important social interactions are and how impactful they are when it comes to learning. I learn new things everyday through my environment and the community. As a teacher, I learn so much from my students and the community that they live in. As an educator, I know how important social aspects in learning are; in particular, I know that my students with autism lack certain social skills and that is a big focus for us. This weeks’ reading has reminded me of why social skills are so important to teach my students. So much learning comes from interacting with others and communicating and collaborating ideas. Learning is influenced by social interactions, interpersonal relationships, and communication with others. As an educator, I try to use social interactions to enhance the learning of all students; the school I am at right now does Peer Buddy Groups. Also, inclusion of my students into general ed classrooms, peer buddy groups, peer modeling, and other social strategies are used throughout our school to better all students and their learning.

Thanks for reading my response to think weeks reading.

classmate 2

 

Learning is a social experience because “all of society and its media are teachers.”, (Phillips, 2009, p.52). From the very beginning of our existence, stimulation and experiences shape the learner, however it is the experiences in which language is involved that make the interaction a social experience for the learner. Instances of social learning is the norm for humans and opportunities for social learning assist in the understanding of morals, history, science, mathematics, literature, and aesthetics, (Phillips, 2009). Social learning is also important outside of academic knowledge, it helps shape our policies, daily actions, and or design of organization and education, (Wenger). Vygotsky even believed that social learning could happen independently and that those who do practice “private speech” are more “socially competent” than other children who do not practice it regularly. Vygotsky’s idea was that high social interaction caused private speech to occur and that it mostly happens during times that require a high cognitive performance.

The fundamental concepts presented by Vygotsky are attention, sensation, perception, and memory. These four functions allow for stronger memories to be created and stored in a more adaptable fashion. Things to be remembered were often paired with something to hold to “remember later” until such strategies were adapted and utilized.

Vygotsky differs from Piaget in the sense that he understand social learning as an independent practice, rather than an event or occurrence that involves another person or form of media. Vygotsky also sees the positive impact of social learning more than Piaget. Piaget focuses much more on the self discovery aspect of learning, which focused on discovery, finding solutions to problems, and restoring cognitive equilibrium. Vygotsky was more focused on what the learner could solve or accomplish with no assistance or guidance.

Communities of practice are essentially the situations and circumstances that teachers create in order for students to have a hands-on, full brain approach to their learning. These communities of practice are similar to that of an apprenticeship, being that the students leave from these communities with a highly sought after skill or trade.

Social constructivists have impacted teaching and learning by outlining the reasons why people learn things in certain situations or by highlighting the scenarios in which learning does not happen. Dewey captures the heart of it with his amazing quote,

“Upon this view, thinking, or knowledge-getting, is far from being the armchair thing it is often supposed to be. The reason it is not an armchair thing is that it is not an event going on exclusively within the cortex or cortex and the vocal organs…Hands and feet, apparatus and appliances of all kinds are as much a part of it as changes with the brain.”, (Phillips, 2009, p.62)

I agree that all teachers should memorize this quote and really take the point to heart with the philosophy they develop their classroom around. Advances in how students learn are significant and are crucial to creating a meaningful atmosphere for students to learn.

These social constructivists relate to me as a student because I was aware that if I asked a friend or someone for help then I would most likely understand it after they help explain it to me. This simple connection goes back to the importance of giving students time to discuss their learning, ask questions, and eliminate misconceptions.

classmate 3

 

Learning is a social experience in that all of us are taught in one way or another by others.  We even see that abandoned children taken in by packs of wild animals learn from those they associate with on a daily basis which is a bit like the modeling Bandura described (Phillips, 59).  While Piaget focused on the internal processes of constructivist learning other thinkers including Vygotsky & Dewey put much more emphasis on social aspects.  McLeod listed five primary differences between Vygotsky and Piaget with Vygotsky citing:

1) Cultural effects

2) Social factors

3) More emphasis on language

4) The importance of adults

5) “Elementary mental functions” that become more sophisticated as students learn.

Vygotsky coined the term Zone of Proximal Development to describe what students are capable of doing with the proper help from other knowledgeable individuals (Phillips, 57).  He also talked about “psychological tools,” such as the language created over time by others, that we need to learn complex concepts (Phillips, 58.) Intuitively any of us who have been around young children know that Vygotsky is right in that we continually facilitate their learning by talking to them, helping them develop their motor functioning, helping them to develop emotion regulation by comforting them when they are upset, and so on.  There is no case when any decent person would leave children to fully fend for themselves.

Other thinkers with similar ideas to Vygotsky include Clifford Geertz who argued that there is no such thing as a common human nature (Phillips, 63) meaning we all have different cultural and social backgrounds that affect our daily learning.  Shirley Brice Heath presented some interesting research on why underprivileged minority children underperformed in their rural school and found part of the problem to be that they were not used to the type of questioning their teachers gave (Phillips, 64) whereby teachers would ask questions they already knew the answer to.  This partially explains why so many students can be really knowledgeable in certain areas but struggle in a traditional school setting.  Anecdotally I see this as I interact with my children when we discuss matters, such as American government, that they know I am an expert on yet answer my questions as part of the learning process.

When Wenger talked about Communities of Practice he was referring to the groups of people with something in common they are working on or towards (Wenger, 211).  As an example, I work with my department at school to make better lessons and with my fellow volunteer soccer coach on methods to improve the skills on our team of three year olds.  It would not be possible to reach my full potential in either endeavor without being able to be social and learn with others.  Anecdotally I have seen in schools where students that are part of a strong Community of Practice, such as those in the band, tend to learn more than those in other areas such as history class that tend to be more solitary in nature.  Ideally we history teachers will find ways to emulate our band colleagues by making our classes more collaborative while also adequately teaching the vast content required by the state.

Social Constructivist approaches to teaching have influenced the way in which we promote peer collaboration (Schunk, 246) and how we see apprenticeships being useful for those learning new job skills (Schunk, 247).  As a teacher I like to promote peer collaboration but cannot always do so given my dual mandate to teach what many students deem boring content and to maintain an orderly classroom.  I do strive though to create more engaging projects like I did last week where 6th grade students learned about mapmaking by creating one on their own and adding features, such as recreational opportunities, that relate to their interests. When done right Social Constructivist practices provide the best learning outcomes but in my experience this also requires somewhat motivated and well-behaved students to accomplish.

2

 

 

3

 

 

THINKING ABOUT EDUCATION SERIES FIFTH EDITION

Jonas F. Soltis, Editor

The revised and expanded Fifth Edition of this series builds on the strengths of the previous editions. Written in a clear and concise style, these books speak directly to preservice and in-service teachers. Each offers useful interpretive categories and thought-provoking insights into daily practice in schools. Numerous case studies provide a needed bridge between theory and practice. Basic philosophical perspectives on teaching, learning, curriculum, ethics, and the relation of school to society are made readily accessible to the reader.

PERSPECTIVES ON LEARNING D. C. Phillips and Jonas F. Soltis

THE ETHICS OF TEACHING Kenneth A. Strike and Jonas F. Soltis

CURRICULUM AND AIMS Decker F. Walker and Jonas F. Soltis

SCHOOL AND SOCIETY Walter Feinberg and Jonas F. Soltis

APPROACHES TO TEACHING Gary D Fenstermacher and Jonas F. Soltis

4

 

 

THINKING ABOUT EDUCATION SERIES

5TH EDITION

5

 

 

PERSPECTIVES ON LEARNING D. C. PHILLIPS

JONAS F. SOLTIS

Teachers College Columbia University New York and London

6

 

 

Published by Teachers College Press, 1234 Amsterdam Avenue, New York, NY 10027

Copyright © 2009 by Teachers College, Columbia University All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopy, or any information storage and retrieval system, without permission from the publisher

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Phillips, D. C. (Denis Charles), 1938-

Perspectives on learning / D. C. Phillips, Jonas F. Soltis. — 5th ed. p. cm. — (Thinking about education series)

Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN: 978-0-8077-4983-8 (pbk.: alk. paper) 1. Learning—Philosophy. I. Soltis, Jonas F. II.

Title.

LB1060.P48 2009 370.15’23–dc22

2009006147 ISBN: 978-0-8077-4983-8 (paper)

e-ISBN: 978-0-8077-7120-4

7

 

 

Contents

Acknowledgments

A Note to the Instructor

Chapter 1 INTRODUCTION

Learning

The Teacher’s Responsibility

The Variety of Theories

An Objection: We Don’t Need Theories, Just Common Sense

The Plan of the Book

Chapter 2 CLASSICAL THEORIES

Plato’s Theory of Learning

Case One

The Lockean Atomistic Model

Case Two

A Critique

Case Three

Chapter 3 BEHAVIORISM

Classical Conditioning

Operant Conditioning

Case One

B. F. Skinner

Strengths and Weaknesses

8

 

 

Case Two

Chapter 4 PROBLEM SOLVING, INSIGHT, AND ACTIVITY

The Gestalt Approach

Case One

The Inquiring Organism

The Mind of the Learner

Chapter 5 PIAGETIAN STRUCTURES AND PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSTRUCTIVISM

The Development of Cognitive Structures

The Principles of Construction

Case One

Some Critical Issues

Guidelines for Educators

Constructivist Approaches to Learning After Piaget

Chapter 6 SOCIAL ASPECTS OF LEARNING

Social Influences on the “Piagetian Child”

John Dewey

Case One

Vygotsky and Others

Case Two

Case Three

Situated Cognition and Legitimate Peripheral Participation in Communities of Practice

Culture and Learning

Chapter 7 COGNITIVE STRUCTURES AND DISCIPLINARY STRUCTURES

Maps and Organizers

An Exercise

9

 

 

The Structure of Disciplines

Bruner, Schwab, and Hirst

An Evaluation

Chapter 8 TRANSFER OF LEARNING

Case One

Related Notions: Mental and Formal Discipline

Case Two

Further Clarifications and Examples

Case Three

Case Four: An Early Empirical Study

Where Do We Stand Today?

Chapter 9 THE COGNITIVE SCIENCE APPROACH

Models: Pros and Cons

The Heuristic Value for Researchers

The Heuristic Value for Teachers

Some Deficiencies of the Computer Model

Understanding, Meaning, and the “Chinese Room”

An Exercise

Case One: Benny’s Mathematics

Plato and the Mind

Chapter 10 ARGUMENTS AND ISSUES

The Relation of Learning Theory to Teaching

Different Kinds of Learning?

A Starting Place for Learning

Learning and Behavior Change

The Scientific Status of Gestalt and Behaviorist Theories

10

 

 

Different Teaching-Learning Strategies

Teaching, Learning, and Stages of Development

Learning to Read

Learning Facts and Structures

Learning Responsibility

Learning Theory and Artificial Intelligence

Learning to Balance Chemical Equations

The Evaluation of Verbal and Skill Learning

Learning the Meaning of Adding

Learning Shakespeare

Culture and Learning

Individualized Learning

A Problem with Multiple Theories of Learning

References, Notes, and Further Reading

Annotated Bibliography

11

 

 

Acknowledgments

As is the case with all books, this one owes much to those who have played a part in its production. Lee Shulman gave encouragement and agreed to use a draft of the first edition of the text in a course co-taught at Stanford with Denis Phillips. We are especially indebted to the students in that course for their constructive criticisms. Professor James Marshall of the University of Auckland carefully read and reacted to several draft chapters. Valerie Phillips and Frances Simon provided essential and much appreciated word-processing skills. For general research assistance that included copyediting, development of cases, and offering useful suggestions, we thank Karl Hostetler. For the second edition, we were guided by several thoughtful reviews of the earlier volume, and we were especially indebted to Kenneth Howe and Robert Floden. The substantial expansion of the discussion of social aspects of learning in the third edition owes much to what was learned from the “Symbolic Systems Seminar in Education” at Stanford over a period of about five years, and Rich Shavelson discussed some issues relevant to the revisions for the fourth and fifth editions. Finally, we thank the able and cooperative staff of TC Press for shepherding us through the various editions.

12

 

 

A Note to the Instructor

This book is designed to be used in the education of teachers. We did not write for “teachers in training” because we believe teachers should be educated rather than trained. We invite the users of the book to think with us as colleagues about the complexities of human learning.

The book is organized so that it can be used in a number of ways to suit the purposes and style of the instructor. It can be used singularly as the primary text for a full course on its topic, as supplemental reading, or as a source for cases and dialogues to stimulate class discussions.

If this book is used as a text in a full course, a number of pedagogical options are available:

1. The first nine chapters can be treated as you would treat any text, and then the arguments and issues in Chapter 10 can be used to provide materials for class discussions for the remainder of the term. From our experience, a case or a dialogue can easily produce a good discussion that lasts thirty or more minutes.

2. We have found that doing a chapter and then spending one or two sessions discussing the cases and related dialogues is a very effective way to mix the theoretical with the practical. At the end of each of the first nine chapters and in Table 1 in Chapter 10 we have offered suggestions for additional cases, dialogues, and issues to be discussed as you proceed.

3. To either of the above approaches could be added your own or class- invented dialogues, debates, and puzzles that apply theory to practice or raise issues of personal concern.

If you have not taught using the case method before, the following suggestions may be of some help:

1. It is important to establish a good group climate for discussion in which individuals feel free to express their views openly without fear of ridicule and also feel free to challenge the honest views of others with reasonable arguments and genuine alternatives.

13

 

 

2. Good group discussions are facilitated by asking students to read cases and sketch their answers to case problems before class so a discussion can start with some forethought and direction.

3. Pedagogically, as a discussion leader it is useful to summarize along the way, to help students see the ideas at issue, and to bring in relevant theoretical knowledge to guide discussions to some reason able conclusion, however firm or tentative.

4. And remember, students can learn worthwhile things even when their instructor is not talking.

We trust you will find this book to be a versatile pedagogical tool, useful in getting students not only to learn about learning theories but also to think with and about them as they make practical applications and raise basic issues.

14

 

 

Chapter 1

15

 

 

Introduction

This is a book about theories of learning. In it we want to get you to think about learning—how it happens, and what it is. Obviously, as a teacher, your job is or will be to help others learn. You may already have some good ideas about learning—after all, you have been doing it yourself for some time. Or you may feel there is not much for you to think about regarding learning since modern learning theorists surely must know all there is to know about it by now. Perhaps all you need to do is read about their theories and heed what they say when you teach or design curricula. Unfortunately, that is not so easy to do. Theorists do not all agree about what learning is or how it happens. Psychologists, anthropologists, linguists, neurophysiologists, philosophers, and others are still trying to understand how people learn. For there are great complexities—there seem to be different types of learning, some involving mental events such as remembering, analyzing, discriminating, and so forth, and some others that involve bodily movements and their coordination, such as when you learn to pitch a baseball. Certainly, theorists and researchers have some good ideas that will help you think about learning, and we will deal with many of them in this book. But ultimately, it is you who will have to make the best sense you can of how to foster various types of human learning in order to become a thoughtful and effective educator.

Learning

To get you into the right frame of mind to think about learning and to help you to see what this book is about, imagine that several of your friends were to contact you and ask a favor. One wants to learn to keep off junk food and seeks your advice and encouragement; the second is trying to learn Spanish vocabulary and asks you to act as tutor; the third has heard you debate in public, admires your skill, and wants your help in learning how to do it for herself; and the fourth friend is learning physics and is stuck on Einstein’s theory, and he asks you to explain it to him. Being generous in nature, and also a very talented person, you agree to help all of them!

Clearly, in all four cases you would be assisting a person to learn. But it is also clear that the types of learning involved are quite different. In the first case you would be helping someone to break a habit (dependence

16

 

 

upon junk food no doubt is partly psychological, but also partly physiological, so what we have here is a learning assignment that involves the mental and the physical realms); in the second you would be helping a person commit information to memory; in the third case you would be teaching your friend a new and complex skill (again this involves the mental/psychological realm and the physical/motor realm); and your fourth friend needs to be taught something quite abstract (and taught so that he achieves that mysterious state we call “understanding”). No doubt you would use different teaching strategies: the method you use to teach your friend to avoid junk food would not work with the learning of debating skills. And rote memorization, which works in the case of foreign words, is not likely to succeed with learning Einstein’s theory. Your friend could memorize it, certainly, but this will not necessarily enable him to understand or apply it intelligently, and that presumably is what he is after.

The Teacher’s Responsibility

How would you go about selecting a suitable teaching strategy in each case? How would you know that it was suitable? If one of your friends failed to learn, would you blame yourself for selecting a poor method? Teachers face these issues all the time, but with added complexity thrown in. They are not usually helping one person at a time, but are trying to promote learning in a class of perhaps thirty or more students. What teaching method would you use if all four of your friends turned up at one time? And how convinced are you that there is a single method or approach that would work adequately in all four cases? Furthermore, you are safe in assuming that your friends want to learn the things they have sought your help with, but this is not always a safe assumption to make in a classroom. Promotion of learning is not unidimensional—the importance of motivating students to learn cannot be emphasized enough; also important is catering for students who have different learning abilities and who cover the work at different rates, deciding what content to teach and what activities to organize in order to facilitate this learning, maintaining discipline, and socializing students to become functioning members of society—all these are grist to the teacher’s mill. Thus, anything you learn will have to be balanced against these other things; a teacher is constantly making difficult “judgment calls.”

This book does not cover all the complexities of a teacher’s life in the classroom—it is a book about theories of learning. In it we can only hope to stimulate you to think about learning, about the forms it takes, and about what you, as a teacher, might do to promote it in students. We cannot

17

 

 

make you a good teacher. You have to do that for yourself. But thinking seriously about theories of learning should help.

The Variety of Theories

At this point you may have become aware of the suspicious fact that we have been using a key word in the plural: “theories” of learning. Using the plural here is in marked contrast with the mainstream tendency over the course of Western thought to treat the learning of propositions (such things as “Sydney is the oldest and largest city in Australia”) as the basic type of learning that should be the starting point for a theory that will apply to all cases of learning. In common with other philosophers, we reject this simplifying assumption.

So, then, why is there more than one theory in this area? There are several answers. In the first place, as we have already illustrated, there is more than one type of learning. It is not clear whether a theory that explains how habits are formed, or how facts are memorized, will also explain how a learner comes to understand a complex and abstract piece of science. (In the field of medicine, the “germ theory of disease” does not explain genetic defects—different types of phenomena require different explanations.) Of course, some researchers who accept the mainstream assumption mentioned above are trying to develop a single comprehensive learning theory; indeed, scientists in many fields are driven to integrate knowledge in this way, for if they are successful the results give a great deal of intellectual satisfaction and solve a number of diverse problems. But so far, in the field of learning, no such attempt has been a resounding success. Indeed, some theorists believe the mind is “modular,” composed of a number of differently functioning systems that have been cobbled together in the course of evolution; others insist that the types of learning are so different that it is unreasonable to expect that a single theory could cover them all.

To help you see what we mean, consider some of the things you have learned in your life so far—and then think about how you learned them. For instance, most of us have learned directly from experience without instruction, study, or practice that ice is cold, flames are hot, water is wet, and knives can cut. However, when we learned the alphabet and how to count to ten, almost certainly we all required a little initial supervised instruction and needed to do some sing-song practicing. But it would be hard to think of learning to play chess or to drive a car without undergoing sustained instruction and without focusing one’s mental efforts on the

18

 

 

tasks embodied in the mastery of such things.

What do these examples suggest? First, there seem to be different sorts of learning, some simple and some complex, some involving the acquisition of knowledge and others involving the mastery of skills and the formation of dispositions. Second, while some things can be learned without a teacher, there are many situations in which the help of a teacher is vital for many learners.

There also is a possibility that different theories of learning have resulted from various investigators approaching the phenomenon of learning from different directions and armed with different initial “hunches.” You may recall the old Indian folk tale about the blind men who were given an elephant to examine. The man who felt the tail got quite a different impression of the beast than the man who felt one of the legs, while the man who started with the trunk reached yet another startling conclusion. So it is in all scientific enquiries—the initial ideas or hypotheses the investigator forms may color his or her later conclusions.

Consider the following possibilities: If one were to focus on how a child learns that flames are hot and take this to be a typical case of learning, a particular (and probably narrow) experiential learning theory most likely would result. But such a theory probably would be different from one that would result from starting with a different case—say, how a child learns to count to ten. Neither of these theories, however, would be likely to be formulated by someone who had selected as a typical case of learning more complicated things like how people learn to drive a car or how high school students learn history. Thus, a psychologist or educational researcher who starts with the insight that humans are part-and-parcel of the animal kingdom may try to explain human learning in the same way that animal learning is explained (say, the learning processes in pigeons or rats). On the other hand, a researcher who regards the human brain as a type of computer, differing from the popular brands largely in that it is made of protoplasm instead of silicon chips, may try to explain as much learning as possible in data-processing terms.

It would be a mistake to think that only researchers hold such divergent, rival views. Teachers, too, vary a great deal in the underlying images they have of the nature of their students. Some regard all members of their school classes as being potentially equal in ability to learn, while others regard the students as inherently quite different; some regard the school as having great power to shape the minds of the students, while

19

 

 

others regard it as being marginally influential at best; some see the students as unwilling and rebellious, while others see them as eager to learn and inclined to behave if they are treated properly.

Whatever your view on these matters, as a professional charged with fostering the intellectual development of your students, you should be acquainted with the variety of theories that have been put forward. Your eyes will be opened to new possibilities, and to facets of your students that you might otherwise not notice. Just as travel broadens the mind, so does acquaintance with rival viewpoints. You should reflect on the various theories of learning, and think about the implications that they have for your work in the classroom. The following chapters should help you set out on this professional journey.

An Objection: We Don’t Need Theories, Just Common Sense

Research in education and the social sciences is sometimes criticized on the ground that it is futile, for it only comes up with “findings” that are so obvious that anyone with common sense knew these things before the research was done. This attitude is particularly common in the realm of teaching; there is nothing mysterious or complex here, for the principles are pretty obvious to anyone who reflects for just a few moments—a book like Perspectives on Learning is quite unnecessary!

Fortunately for us, as authors, there is a decisive two-pronged answer to this. First, there actually has been some research on what people regard as “obvious.”1 Several decades ago a student of the great educational psychologist Nathaniel Gage drew up two lists of supposed “findings” of social science research; the second list contained the opposites of the items on the first list. (List one might have items like “teenage girls are better at Z than boys,” while the second list would have “teenage girls are not as good as boys at Z.”) A large number of laypeople were shown one or the other of the lists (nobody, of course, was shown both lists), and asked to judge whether or not each of the reported “findings” was so obvious that the research should not have been done. In many cases, both of the contradictory findings were judged to be so obvious that the result was commonsensical! The moral here, of course, is that we need to be cautious about what we judge to be commonsense knowledge. (And recall that our ancestors thought it was commonsense that the world was flat, and that the cure for many diseases—possibly including anemia—was to “bleed” the patient.)

The second point in the answer to the objection that all we need to

20

 

 

foster learning is common sense is that there is often bias in the selection of examples; clearly there are some occasions when research confirms the “obvious,” but we should not overemphasize these and ignore the many important cases where the answer to the question is not obvious at all. (Nor should we downplay the importance of actually confirming the obvious!) Is it obvious, before research, which method of teaching reading —“phonics” or “whole language”—is most effective and what the unintended harmful consequences of each might be? Is it obvious, in teaching a new mathematics skill, whether or not “massed practice” is superior to “distributed practice” (that is, giving a large number of practice exercises in a clump, or spreading the practice out over a somewhat extended time frame)? Is it obvious, before research, what the limitations to human memory are? If gender differences are found in some educational performance, is it obvious before research whether the difference is due to biological/developmental or sociocultural factors?

The Plan of the Book

We will start with a consideration of two classical theories of learning that may appear simple and a little strange to modern eyes. But we will try to show that Plato’s “recollection” theory and Locke’s “blank tablet” theory offer some interesting ways to think about learning and set some problems and issues with which modern theories are still trying to deal.

Then we will look at behaviorism, a theory of learning that dominated the field of psychology for a large part of the twentieth century. The behaviorist takes learning to be the result of actions of the environment on the learner. For instance, we learn that a lightning flash is soon followed by thunder and so we also may learn to cover our ears whenever we see lightning. Sometimes we find our environment and our actions in it to be rewarding and so we learn to repeat actions that generally result in something nice happening to us. People who are good at ping-pong and frequently win tend to play more often than those who lose every match. According to this behaviorist theory, we learn to act in acceptable ways by being praised when we do good things and by praise being withheld when we do not.

The behaviorist theory has been challenged by a number of other theories and we shall consider the major challengers in subsequent chapters. Gestalt theory views learning as a process involving the attempt to think things out and then having “it all come together” suddenly in the mind. Sometimes it is jokingly referred to as the “Aha!” or “Got it!” theory

21

 

 

of learning or, more seriously, the “insight” theory. It is like poring over your class notes before an exam and finally coming to see how the ideas dealt with relate to one another. To explain this mental phenomenon, the Gestalt psychologists looked beyond behavior and the environment, and they tried to throw light on learning by investigating tendencies of the mind to pattern and structure experience.

Beginning with a hunch about the importance of firsthand experience to learning, John Dewey developed a “problem solving” theory of learning whose basic premise was that learning happens as a result of our “doing” and “experiencing” things in the world as we successfully solve real problems that are genuinely meaningful to us. School learning then, he argued, must be based on meaningful student experiences and genuine student problem solving. He believed that textbook problems most often were not real problems to students and that school learning should be an experientially active, not a passive, affair.

Taking a biological approach, Piaget viewed learning as an adaptive function of an organism. By means of learning, an organism develops “schemes” for dealing with and understanding its environment. For Piaget, learning is the individual’s construction and modification of structures for dealing successfully with the world. He also claimed that there are stages of intellectual development that all human beings pass through as they learn certain universal schemes for structuring the world (like the concepts of number, cause, time, and space) and as they learn certain aspects of logical reasoning. Piaget’s ideas have inspired many subsequent theorists of learning, including the so-called radical constructivists.

A defect in many of the preceding theories is that they consider learning to be an individual phenomenon—the learner is depicted as a lone inquirer. In fact, of course, learners are embedded in a social network; teachers, parents, siblings, and peers, not to mention characters on TV and in films, all influence what each of us will learn. Chapter 6 discusses some basic ideas related to this theme of the social dimension of learning from Dewey, Vygotsky, and Bandura down to the advocates of “situated learning” and participation in communities of practice. Chapter 7 returns to the notion of “structure,” this time with regard to the subject matter to be learned. Since subjects are organized bodies of knowledge, it might help learners if they could see or construct for themselves the basic outline or structure of the subject they are studying. Dewey, Bruner, Schwab, and Hirst offer some insights into this process. One of the justifications for teaching the structure of a subject is that this facilitates using the material

22

 

 

in new contexts—and this is a segue to the age-old issue of transfer of learning. For literally thousands of years it has been held that a major aim of education is to train the mind so that the skills acquired and strengthened in one context can be applied to solving novel problems in other domains. The form this doctrine has taken over the centuries, and how it fares in the light of contemporary research, is the topic of Chapter 8.

Finally, in Chapter 9, we shall look at an emerging theory of learning that comes out of our contemporary technological revolution in computing and artificial intelligence. This approach to learning theory has been called various things but perhaps the best catch-all term for it is the “cognitive science” approach. As we think about learning from this point of view we will have to consider to what extent computers are modeled on human minds and to what extent we can understand minds and learning by treating them as “computerlike.” There may be as many puzzles as there are answers and insights offered by this emerging view, but we know that it is one that has stimulated much contemporary thinking about learning and is sure to be of import to educators in the future.

The last chapter in this book, Chapter 10, is somewhat different from the others. It is one we hope you will refer to and use as you go through the book itself because it is designed to stimulate further thought about the theories, problems, and issues raised in the book. We call this last chapter “Arguments and Issues.” In it there are eighteen vignettes—concrete cases in the form of dialogues, disputes, arguments, and debates—that raise interesting and important issues about learning, and bring theory closer to practice. Whether you refer to some of the cases in Chapter 10 as you go along, or save them for consideration at the end, we are sure you will find that class discussions of these examples will force even deeper thinking about learning and educating. For those who wish to sample some cases relevant to this first chapter before going on to Chapter 2, we recommend “The Relation of Learning Theory to Teaching” and “Different Kinds of Learning?” in Chapter 10. The book ends with references and additional recommendations for further reading that will take you beyond our introductory treatment of theories of learning and keep you thinking about them as you become a professional educator.

23

 

 

Chapter 2

24

 

 

Classical Theories

Interest in teaching and learning is not new; it probably antedates recorded history. The New Testament paints a picture of Jesus as a dedicated teacher, consistently using stories and examples that would communicate his ideas in a memorable way to his audiences. A few years earlier, Rabbi Hillel also won fame as a teacher. Going back further, the ancient Greek philosopher Plato (428?–347 B.C.E.) expounded his ideas in lively dialogues, and his Academy was famous as a teaching institution. Plato, too, was concerned to use examples and stories that would make an impact. All this, of course, reflects the unsurprising insight that it is most effective to present material in a way that is both interesting and understandable to those who are to learn it.

But there is a problem here, and it is a tribute to Plato’s genius that he was able to perceive it. How is it that a learner is able to understand something new? Consider a person who was absolutely and completely ignorant; how could this person understand, and learn, something that was totally incomprehensible? (Could a computer, with completely empty data banks and no internal program, acquire a piece of factual information without any prior preparation?) Plato had one of the characters in his dialogue Meno raise the issue in this way:

I know, Meno, what you mean … you argue that a man cannot inquire either about that which he knows, or about that which he does not know; for if he knows, he has no need to inquire; and if not, he cannot; for he does not know the very subject about which he is to inquire.1

This problem, in one form or another, continues to plague researchers to the present day.

One answer that occurs after a little reflection is that learning depends upon the student having some prior knowledge or experience. A child who has not yet learned a language, and a computer that has not yet been programmed, cannot have anything “explained” to them. People listening to Plato or Hillel or Jesus would not be able to learn if they did not have enough experience to comprehend the parable being presented. A student who does not know that light has a velocity, and who does not have some understanding of the concepts of mass and energy, could not learn Einstein’s theory (at least in the sense of understanding it and its

25

 

 

implications).

Further reflection shows that, as it stands, this solution is no solution at all—at best it pushes the problem one stage back. For where did this previous knowledge come from? How was it learned? Presumably it was able to be learned because something prior to it was known. But, in turn, how was this learned? Here we are in the grip of an infinite regress—an uncomfortable situation to be in. Learning is possible only if some prior things are known, and these prior things could have been learned only if something prior to them had been learned, and so on!

Plato’s Theory of Learning

The specifics of Plato’s own solution to this problem seem rather fanciful to the modern reader, but the principle he adopted to escape from the infinite regress is one that is still in use: knowledge is innate, it is in place in the mind at birth. At the end of his famous work, The Republic, Plato included a myth describing the adventures of a young soldier, Er, who appeared to have been slain in battle, but who revived nearly two weeks later and was able to describe what had happened to his soul during the time he seemed to be dead. Er, together with the souls of those who actually had died, was able to gaze on the realm of everlasting reality, and thus come to learn the truth. Er also witnessed how souls picked new lives, and he saw that just before they were reborn the souls camped overnight on the banks of the Forgetful River. They were forced to drink from the river, where some drank more than their fair portion; by the middle of the night all souls had forgotten all that they had seen in heaven, and then they were swept away to their new lives on Earth. The strong implication is that those who drank too fully would not be able, in the new life, to remember anything about reality, and these individuals would remain ignorant. Those who had drunk only the minimum, however, could with great effort—and with the prompting of education on Earth—recall the insights into reality their souls had received. These latter would be the people who, on Earth, would be regarded as having learned. In other words, for Plato learning was a process of recalling what the soul had already seen and absorbed; his theory (if we can call it that) even explains why it is that some people can learn more, or can learn more readily, than others. For Plato, teaching is simply the helping of this remembering process.

In the other dialogue we have mentioned, Meno, there is a famous passage in which a slave boy—who has never had any geometry lessons— is led by a series of questions to invent for himself a theorem related to

26

 

 

that of Pythagoras, which states that the square of the hypotenuse of a right triangle is equal to the sum of the squares of the other two sides. The point is the same as in “The Myth of Er”; the slave boy apparently has learned something of which he was previously totally ignorant, but in fact it would be impossible for him to do so, and really what has happened is that he has recalled something that was in his soul (or, if you would prefer, in his mind) all the time. According to Plato, if one does not previously know something, one cannot learn it now! In later chapters of this book we will see how twentieth-century researchers faced up to Plato’s problem—their solutions are no less wonderful.

There is another important facet to Plato’s view of learning, one which some—but not all—recent writers have explicitly opposed. In an important respect Plato regarded learning as a rather passive process in which impressions are made upon the receptive soul or mind. After all, Er learned by observing the realities in heaven. Plato tells another story, “The Simile of the Cave,” about some prisoners chained in a cave so that they can look only at the wall furthest away from the entrance. Outside the cave people pass by, carrying various objects held high above their heads, but the prisoners can only see the shadows of the objects on the wall. What they learn in their world of the cave is about these shadows, which they mistake for knowledge of reality. Only if they are released and allowed to turn around will they come to see reality and acquire (learn) real knowledge. Plato was pointing out that many people who think they are knowledgeable actually are quite mistaken. They take appearance to be reality.

According to this simile, then, teaching is the process of releasing people from the chains of ignorance; but it is also clear that learning is passive, that it is a matter of “turning” and allowing the mind to see clearly. In other places Plato spelled out more clearly what is involved here, and it is obvious that he valued the place of abstract reasoning; the person who had been trained to reason clearly (logically and mathematically) would be more likely to escape from the cave of ignorance and see the truth by using his mind. But nevertheless seeing the truth was a kind of seeing. (And, of course, we still say “I see it” when we have learned something!) These points emerge in the following portion of Plato’s dialogue:

We must reject the conception of education professed by those who say that they can put into the mind knowledge that was not there before—rather as if they could put sight into blind eyes.

27

 

 

It is a claim that is certainly made.

But our argument indicates that this capacity is innate in each man’s mind, and that the faculty by which he learns is like an eye which cannot be turned from darkness to light unless the whole body is turned; in the same way the mind as a whole must be turned away from the world of change until it can bear to look straight at reality…. Isn’t that so?

Yes.

Then this business of turning the mind around might be made a matter of professional skill, which would effect the conversion as easily and effectively as possible. It would not be concerned to implant sight, but to ensure that someone who had it already was turned in the right direction and looking the right way.2

Case One

To help you think about the points Plato is making, imagine this teacher– pupil interaction:

 

P. Mrs. Smith, I can’t figure out the answer to this math puzzle.

T: Which one, Henry?

P: The one that says, If you know that there are six grapes and two plums for each person sitting at a table and that there is a total of twenty-four pieces of fruit on the table, then you should know how many people are seated at the table … but I don’t.

T Sure you do. Think a minute. Could there be only one person?

P: No.

T: Why?

P: Because one person would get only six grapes plus two plums and that’s eight pieces of fruit and there are more than that.

T: How many more?

P: Sixteen.

T: And if each person gets eight pieces, how many more people could there be?

P: Two! So there must be three people seated at the table!

T: See, I told you that you knew the answer. You just needed to get yourself in a position to see it.

 

Did the teacher tell or explain anything to the pupil? Did the teacher

28

 

 

teach? Did the pupil learn something? What? Do you think this is an example of Plato’s theory of learning? Why or why not? If you think about this case, and perhaps discuss it with others, we think you will see why Plato’s myths and similes have stimulated the imagination of his readers for more than two thousand years.

Nevertheless, it is clear that the general answer Plato gave to the question “How is learning possible?” is not acceptable. If people can learn only if they have previous knowledge, then it is no solution to say that the soul acquired this previous knowledge sometime earlier by means of a process of observation. For how could the soul learn by observing unless it already knew something? (Imagine a computer wired to a TV camera—a setup found in modern robots; the camera may “observe” the surroundings but unless the computer is programmed no information will be stored.) It is apparent that we are still in the grip of the infinite regress: Where did the original knowledge (or program) come from?

The Lockean Atomistic Model

A major attempt to answer this question was made nearly two thousand years after Plato. At the end of the seventeenth century the British philosopher John Locke (1632–1704) developed a theory of learning that was to profoundly influence the early development of modern psychology, as well as shape educational practice down to the present day. Locke shared some of Plato’s assumptions but disagreed with him about others. Locke could not accept that knowledge was innate; in his view the infant came into the world with a mind that was completely devoid of content—it was like an “empty cabinet,” a “blank tablet,” or a “tabula rasa.” On the other hand, Locke seems to have realized that something had to be present for the child to be able to learn.

Modern technology gives us an advantage that Locke did not have; there is a familiar and simple example that now can be used to illustrate the principles he had in mind. These days just about all of us have purchased a hand-held electronic calculator. It comes from the factory nicely packaged; when it is turned on it lights up but nothing else happens, for it has no contents in its memory. It is exactly analogous to Locke’s newborn baby—it is a “blank slate.” But lying dormant within the calculator are various powers or abilities or capacities to perform operations. The device lies ready to perform multiplications and additions, calculate percentages and square roots, commit numbers to memory, and so on. These powers or capacities have been wired in by the

29

 

 

manufacturers.

Similarly, Locke realized that the human infant is born with certain biologically preformed abilities, but these lie dormant. He was, of course, thinking about these matters long before the theory of evolution was developed, and he had no way to explain how the human species had come to acquire the various capacities and systems that it possesses. But just as the body was born with certain potentialities, so it was—for Locke—with the mind:

In this faculty of repeating and joining together its ideas, the mind has greater power in varying and multiplying the objects of its thoughts…. It can, by its own power, put together those ideas it has, and make new complex ones.3

The mental powers or faculties that allow learning to take place, then, are “wired in”—they are part of the biological equipment of the human species. But these powers require ideas to work upon; they require some mental content. How does Locke account for the acquisition of these initial ideas? Again the analogy of the calculator is helpful. In order to use the device we must punch in some basic data via the keyboard; we may feed in, for example, 3 + 5 =___. Only when some numbers are put “inside” the calculator will its powers come into operation. And these numbers come from the calculator’s outside environment. So it is with humans. Locke’s words are famous:.

Let us then suppose the mind to be, as we say, white paper void of all characters, without any ideas. How comes it to be furnished? Whence comes it by that vast store which the busy and boundless fancy of man has painted on it with an almost endless variety? Whence has it all the materials of reason and knowledge? To this I answer, in one word, from EXPERIENCE. In that all our knowledge is founded; and from that it ultimately derives itself.4

Locke’s account of learning, then, is as follows: The newborn baby knows nothing, but it immediately starts to have experience of its environment via its senses. It sees shapes and colors, it hears things, it tastes and touches and smells. The resulting simple ideas (as Locke calls them) are retained because the mind has the power of memory. Gradually the child will use his or her powers of combination, abstraction, and so on to build up complex ideas. The child also will experience certain “internal” phenomena, such as concentration, puzzlement, love, and rage, and from this there will be acquired certain other simple ideas that will be added to the rest. But no simple idea can be invented; if the child has not had the necessary experience, the simple idea will be missing, and this in turn will limit what can be produced in the way of complex ideas. A corollary of this is that all complex ideas can be traced back to the combination of a

30

 

 

certain number of simple ideas.

It is easy for a modern reader to underestimate the power of Locke’s simple model of learning. But its relevance for the work of the teacher is great. In the late nineteenth century several researchers realized that the early years of schooling were not as effective as they might be, because young children were assumed by teachers to have had more experience than actually was the case. Surveys in the United States, for example, showed that many of those starting school in urban centers had never seen common farm animals (some children thought that cows were only an inch or so large, because they had only seen drawings of them in picture books); many did not know more than a few colors, and others had never seen the sea. More recently, in the 1960s, we realized that children from low-income families lack a great many of the basic concepts that those coming from more affluent homes have acquired, and researchers hypothesized that this is one reason why many children quickly become low achievers in school. The U.S. federal government’s “Operation Head Start” and the TV program Sesame Street were attempts to remedy this situation. Montessori schools, too, place a great deal of emphasis on the early sense experience of children, and they use a graded series of exercises with blocks of different colors, shapes, and textures.

All of these things are very much in the Lockean spirit; if children have not had a certain experience, then they will lack the related simple ideas, and as a result there may be deficiencies in the complex ideas they can build up (for some of the simple building blocks will be missing). One of the lasting contributions made by Locke is to alert us to the issue of prerequisites for learning: What experiences or simple ideas must a child have had in order to be able to go ahead and learn some new material? Teachers, in helping children to learn, do not think of this issue as often, perhaps, as they should. It is interesting to draw a contrast with computer programmers—in getting a computer to “learn” to perform some task, nothing can be taken for granted, and absolutely everything that the computer needs to “know” must be fed in. One slight omission, and the computer will not be able to perform in the desired manner. Maybe we should work on the principle that the same is true of human learners!

Case Two

Imagine the following teaching-learning episode. Ask yourself as you read it, does it illustrate Locke’s theory? Can Plato’s theory explain it?

 

31

 

 

T: Today, class, we are going to try to understand the theory of continental drift. Who can tell me what a continent is? Peter?

P: A continent is a very large land mass like North America or Africa.

T: And, of course, we all know what drift is, don’t we? It’s like putting a leaf in a stream and watching it move wherever the current pushes it. You’ve all seen that happen, haven’t you?

Class: Yesss!

T: Now let’s look at the map. If you could move North and South America across the Atlantic Ocean, how would those continents fit against the continents of Europe and Africa? Mary?

M: Quite well. I never thought of it that way, but it’s just like tearing a piece of cardboard and putting the torn edges back together again.

T: Do you think it’s possible that long ago North and South America were connected to Europe and Africa in one large land mass which then broke off and drifted apart?

M: Looks possible, but how could something as heavy and solid as a continent drift across an ocean? Aren’t the continents attached to the earth’s crust?

T: Have you ever watched a pot of soup boil? The water bubbles up and pushes solid pieces in the soup away from the center toward the sides of the pot. Geologists believe that the inner core of the earth is hot molten matter that creates currents like those in a boiling pot. They have found a rift line in the middle of the Atlantic Ocean which is a thin part of the earth’s crust and is made up of newer materials than the continents. So they hypothesize that the hot inner core of the Earth leaks out at this “rift” and pushes the continents further and further away from each other since they first broke apart millions of years ago.

M: So, it’s like the leaf drifting on the stream or pieces in a soup pot. The continents move because of the liquid movements below them. I see!

T: Class, any questions?

Class: Nooooo!

 

Before you read on you may find it interesting to go back to the “fruit on the table” case. Can Locke’s theory of mental powers or faculties of

32

 

 

reasoning explain what’s happening to the pupil solving the math puzzle? Which theory, Plato’s or Locke’s, seems more satisfactory for interpreting the problem about fruit? Why? We shall revisit Locke’s theory briefly in Chapter 5 when we discuss modern “radical constructivists.”

A Critique

It would be a mistake, however, to think that the Lockean model of learning is perfect. One defect that Locke shares with Plato is the passive picture that is presented of the learner, especially during the early stages of the acquisition of knowledge. For Plato, the pupil was a spectator of reality; and for Locke, the mind was like an empty cabinet waiting to be filled. Very few things are as inert as a cabinet! As we will see in later chapters, more recent theorists of learning have emphasized the activity— both physical and mental—of the learner. Perhaps Locke had never closely observed a young baby, but certainly he missed the significance of the constant handling, sucking, and probing that goes on as the child learns about the world. To Locke, and probably Plato, experience is something that happens to a learner; but to more recent learning theorists, experience is something that a learner engages in, something that transpires as a result of the interaction between a learner and the surroundings. The philosopher and educationist John Dewey put it nicely; writing about American schools early in the twentieth century, he said that

those under instruction are too customarily looked upon as acquiring knowledge as theoretical spectators, minds which appropriate [gain] knowledge by direct energy of intellect. The very word pupil has almost come to mean one who is engaged not in having fruitful experiences but in absorbing knowledge directly.5

Dewey noted that the mind, the “organ” for acquiring knowledge, traditionally was conceived as being quite unrelated to “the physical organs of activity,” and activity of the body was regarded as having nothing to do with learning. Indeed, activity was thought “to be an irrelevant and intruding physical factor.” In contrast, Dewey stressed the link between learning and doing. He was a powerful critic of Plato and Locke, and he was a pioneer of “activity methods” in the classroom. We will examine his theory of learning in more detail later.

Another interesting aspect of Locke that has come under criticism is his atomism. Locke was a friend of the famous physicist Sir Isaac Newton and was much impressed by the method Newton had used—the method of breaking a physical system down (in theory) into its smallest parts, “atoms” or “corpuscles,” and then studying what happened to these. In other words, Newton started with small particles and gradually pieced

The Five Forces Model of Competition

Liberty University – BUSI 690BUSI690CH3hwk.docx

Liberty University – BUSI 690 BUSI690 CH3 hwk

1

The Five Forces Model of Competition

The character and complexities of competitive forces are rarely the same from one industry to another and must be thoroughly understood to answer such questions as: “Where are we now?” Michael Porter’s Five Forces Competitive Model is the most widely used tool in business today in determining the competitive intensity and therefore attractiveness of a particular industry.

2

Strategic Group Mapping

Read the overview below and complete the activities that follow.

A strategic group consists of those industry members with similar competitive approaches and positions in the market. Companies in the same strategic group can resemble one another in any of several ways: They may have comparable product-line breadth, sell in the same price/quality range, emphasize the same distribution channels, use essentially the same product attributes to appeal to similar types of buyers, depend on identical technological approaches, or offer buyers similar services and technical assistance. Illustration Capsule 3.1 presents a two-dimension diagram reflecting how rivals in the U.S. casual dining industry are positioned.

Based on the strategic group map in Illustration Capsule 3.1, which casual dining chains are Cracker Barrel’s closest competitors? Explain your answer.

3

With which strategic group does Panera Bread Company compete the least, according to the map? Explain your answer.

4

Why do you think no casual dining chains are positioned in the area above the Olive Garden group? Explain your answer

5

The kinds of factors that might be reviewed when considering the “Economic” aspect of the PESTEL includeTop of Form

6

The impact of baby boomers getting older on an industry would be classified in which PESTEL factor?

7

Effective use of the PESTEL framework can help us identify